book excerptise:   a book unexamined is wasting trees

The philosophy of grammar

Otto Jespersen

Jespersen, Otto;

The philosophy of grammar

G. Allen & Unwin, 1924/1968, 359 pages

topics: |  linguistics |


Much debate in today's linguistics - between the rule-driven excesses of
Chomskyan models and the confused pragmatics of the cognitive grammarians
- hinges on whether grammar is a set of rules or a formula.  The Chomskyan
admits that grammar in languages as they are actually used often include
many mixups between the rule-based parts (syntax) and the formulaic parts
(lexicon).  However, he further argues that owing to its variabilty the
actual language as spoken (e-language) is too amorphous to be studied, and
that the only type of grammar worth investigating is of the rule variety
(i-language).  The proper scope of linguistics should be to study the ideal
language that the user knows (competence) but may fail to produce
(performance).  Of course, this position has been strongly critiqued, even
By William Labov: 

	It is now evident to many linguists that the primary purpose of the
	distinction (competence/ performance) has been to help the linguist
	exclude data which he finds inconvenient to handle -- that is, to
	further the restricted definition of linguistics set out by Chomsky
	in Aspects (1965:3).
		- The notion of 'System' in creole studies
		from Pidginization and Creolization of Languages, 1971, p.468


On the other hand, the Cognitive (or usage-driven) grammarian says that
grammar is a continuum - graded from aspects that are more rule like, and
others that are less.  Grammar needs to address both these aspects.  One of
its primary tools that enable it to do this is the involvement of semantics
in the grammatical enterprise.

Jespersen, grand old dad of linguistics

Generations of earlier linguists have written eloquently on this propensity
for rules to mix comfortably with fuzzy areas like pragmatics and language
change.   In the 19th and 20th centuries, the historical turn in
linguistics culminated in the magnificient achievement (in the English
language) of the Oxford English Dictionary.  This philological enterprise
gave rise to an explanation for many of the processes of language change
that informs Jespersen's narrative. 

Type vs Formula: plural formed through the addition of -en to the singuIar : only surviving instance is oxen, which is living as a formula, though its type is extinct.

However, subsequent to the rule-based revolution fostered by computers, and the symbolic movement in AI that followed, Chomsky in his analysis returned to the 17th c. Port-Royal grammarians and their Cartesian roots in order to justify his strong rule-driven position, and invoked the separation of syntax from everything else in cognition.


In the 1960s, the idea of autonomous syntax swept through linguistics,
riding on the back of the more general generative grammar proposal for
formal analysis of syntax.  The glimmerings of a formal theory for a
subject that had become increasingly descriptive and amorphous, brought in
a sea change and despite strong opposition originating in the second
decade, these ideas continued to dominate linguistic research for four
decades.

In the 1990s, with the growing realization of the importance of the
subconscious and the relevance of implicit processes even for language
production and understanding, the rule-driven, deliberative stance
gradually weakened.  Indeed, the autonomous syntax position within the
generativist tradition seems rather moribund today, compared to the
thriving work going on in cognitive and usage-based models

It is a pleasure today to read this work by a towering figure of
linguistics, whose insights into this debate are outlined beautifully in
the first chapter, and indeed, throughout this eminently readable, but
sadly very hard to obtain text.  All of Jespersen's writings deserve to be
much more widely read.  [Reprint publishers take note].  Needless to say,
much that Jespersen says goes against the grain of Chomskyan theorizing.

Also see his inimitable Growth and Structure of the English Language (1905).

					[review AM sep 2012 ed. dec 2015]



Excerpts

Introduction by James McCawley


In PG, Jespersen provides a critical examination of a large number of
grammatical concepts, distinguishing clearly among notions that linguists
often confuse even today (such as the notions of "subject," "topic,"
and "agent," which even Leonard Bloomfield couldn't keep straight) and
paying attention to a far broader range of examples than scholars of his
time or even of ours were accustomed to dealing with (as when he discusses
examples such as Catch me going there in his chapter on "Negation").
He notices the implications of details in standard definitions and
shows how they often misrepresent the facts, e.g., traditional definition
of third person as "person or thing spoken of" is inaccurate, since one
still uses first and second person forms when speaking about oneself or
one's addressee; here an accurate definition must be negative: "does not
include speaker or addressee," and even that definition must be qualified
to allow for forms such as your humble servant and madame that are "notionally"
first and second person but "formally" third person. The thoroughness
of Jespersen's coverage of many classes of syntactic constructions
in English is astonishing, as in his treatment of full and reduced
sentential complements in chapter 9. There are also gratifyingly thorough
treatments of syntactic constructions that linguists have largely ignored,
as in his brief but highly comprehensive treatment of "comparative
conditional" sentences such as The more he gets, the more he wants,
which includes the only successful attempt that I am aware of to assimilate
the semantics of sentences such as It grew darker and darker to that of
comparative conditionals.

The unusual amount of effort that Jespersen put into PG is reflected
in the fifteen years that he spent working on it and the three changes of
title (for which, see Jespersen's preface) that it underwent during its long
gestation. As in his Language, the other large semipopular work that he
completed as he was approaching his retirement in 1925 from the faculty
of the University of Copenhagen, he cannibalized many of his earlier
works in writing it. Each of the chapters deals with a topic on which he
could easily have written an entire book, and in one case he already had
written one: his 150-page 1917 monograph, Negation in English and Other
Languages, of which chapter 24, "Negation," is a distillation.

Excerpts

--from preface

This book has taken long in making, and like other pet children, it has borne
many names. When I gave the first crude sketch of it as a series of lectures
at Columbia University in 1909-10, I called it an Introduction to English
Grammar; in the preface of the second volume of my Modern English Grammar
(1914) I was rash enough to refer to "a forthcoming book on The Basis of
Grammar"; in Lantguage (1922) I spoke of it again as "a future work, to be
called, probably, The Logic of Grammar," and now at last I venture to present
it under the perhaps too ambitious title of "The Philosophy of Grammar." It
is an attempt at a connected presentation of my views of the general
principles of grammar [based on my long study] of various languages and
preparing an extensive work on English Grammar, of which I have
so far been able to bring out only two volumes.

Chapter I: Living Grammar


Speaker and Hearer


The essence of language is human activity - activity on the part of
one individual to make himself understood by another, and activity
on the part of that other to understand what was in the mind of
the first. [opening lines]

Language as the spoken form

The grammarian must be ever on his guard to avoid the pitfalls
into which the ordinary spelling is apt to lead him. Let me give
a few very elementary instances. The ending for the plural of
substantives and for the third person singular of the present tense
of verbs is in writing the same -s in such words as ends, locks, rises,
but in reality we have three different endings, as seen when we
transcribe them phonetically [endz, loks, raiziz]. Similarly the
written ending -ed covers three different spoken endings in sailed,
locked, ended, phonetically [seld, lokt, endid].    p.18

In the written language it looks as if the preterites paid and said were
formed in the same way, but differently from stayed, but in reality paid
and stayed are formed regularly [paid, steid], whereas said is irregular
as having its vowel shortened [sed].  Where the written language recognizes
only one word there, the spoken language distinguishes two both as to sound
and signification (and grammatical import), as seen in the sentence "There
were many people there." [pron. second has eps in middle]

Even without any special grammatical training we feel that the two sentences
	John gave Mary the apple,
	My uncle lent the joiner five shillings,
are analogous, that is, they are made after the same pattern.

how do such types come into existenoe in the mind of a speaker?  [an infant],
without any grammatical instruction, from innumerable sentences heard and
understood he will abstract some notion of their struoture which is definite
enough to guide him in framing sentences of his own, though it is difficult
or impossible to state what that notion is except by means of technical terms
like subject, verb, etc.

Types (free expressions) vs Formulas


FREE EXPRESSIONS : created on the spur of the moment after a certain type
   which has come into existence in the speaker's subconsciousness as a
   result of his having heard many sentences possessing some trait or
   traits in common...

It follows that the distinction between them and FORMULAS ("how do you do?",
"beg your pardon") cannot always be discovered except through a fairly close
analysis.

The distinction between formulas and free expressions pervades all parts of
grammar. In morphology we have the same distinction with regard to fiexional
forms. The plural eyen was going out of use in the sixteenth century...
The only surviving instance of a plural formed through the addition of -en to
the singular is oxen, which is living as a formula, though its type is
extinct.

Meanwhile, skoen, fone, eyen, kine have been supplanted by shoes, foes,
eyes, cows; that is, the plural of these words has been reshaped in
accordance with the living type found in kings, lines, stones, etc. 21

When eyes was first uttered instead of eyen, it was an analogical
formation on the type of the numerous words which already had -s in the
plural.  
[as with over-regularization in children's speech e.g. "goed", 
see Computational explorations in cognitive neuroscience: understanding the mind by simulating the brain by Randall C. O'Reilly and Yuko Munakata (2000).]

It will be seen that in morphology what was above called a
"type" is the same thing as the principle of what are generally
called regular formations, while irregular forms are "formulas."
[type approximates what Langacker calls "schema"]

An example of a productive suffix is _-ness_, because it is possible to
form new words like weariness, oloseness, perverseness, etc. On the
contrary -lock in wedlock is unproductive, and so is -th in width, breadth,
health, and no [new] word with this ending seems to have come into
existence for several hundred years.

The distinction between a formula and a free combination also affects
word-order. One example may suffice:

	so long as SOME+THING is felt as a free combination of two elements,
	another adjective may be inserted in the usual way: some good thing.
	But as soon as SOMETHING has become a fixed formula, it is
	inseparable, and the adjective has to follow: something good.
	Compare also the difference between the old "They turned each to
	other" and the modern "they turned to each other."
	[presumably a fusion of each-other?]

Gradation in regular / irregular forms: types vs idioms


The coalescence of originally separate elements into a formula
is not always equally complete: in BREAKFAST it is shown not only
by the pronunciation [brekfest] as against [breik, fa·st], but also
by forms like he breakfasts, breakfasted (formerly breaks fast, broke
fast), but in TAKE PLACE the coalescence is not carried through to the
same extent, and yet this must be recognized as a formula in the
sense 'come to happen,' as it is impossible to treat it in the same
way as take with another object, which in some combinations can
be placed first (a book he took) and which can be made the subject in
the passive (the book was taken), neither of which is possible in the
case of take place.

[The] distinction here established between formulas and free combinations has
been shown to pervade the whole domain of linguistic activity. A formula may
be a whole sentence or a group of words, or it may be one word, or it may be
only part of a word,-that is not important, but it must always be something
which to the actual speech-instinct is It unit which cannot be further
analyzed or decomposed in the way a free combination can.

Grammatical habits (generalization)


Grammatical habits may thus lead to what from one point of view may be termed
redundancy: e.g. the use of it in many cases.  It became an invariable
custom to have a subject before the verb, and therefore a sentence which did
not contain a subject was felt to be incomplete. In former times no pronoun
was felt to be necessary with verbs like Latin pluit, ningit 'it rains, it
snows,' etc.; thus Italian still has piove, nevica, but on the analogy of
innumerable such expressions as I come, he comes, etc., the pronoun it was
added in E. it rains, it snowsd, and correspondingly in French, German,
Danish and other languages: il pleut, es regnet, det regner.

It has been well remarked that the need for this pronoun was especially felt
when it became the custom to express the difference between affirmation and
question by means of word-order (er kommt, kommt er )...

Pleonastic "it is"; auxiliary "do"


Verbs like rain, snow had originally no subject, and as it would be hard
even now to define logically what the subject it stands for and what it
means, many scholars ~look upon it as simply a grammatioal device to make
the sentence conform to the type most generally found.  In other cases there
is a real subject. yet we are led for some reason or other to insert the
pronoun it.  It is possible to say. for instance. "To find one's way in
London is not easy," but more often we find it convenient not to introduce
the infinitive at once; in which cases, however, we do not begin with the
verb and say "Is not easy to find one's way in London," because we are
accustomed to look upon sentences beginning with a verb as interrogative; so
we say "It is not easy," etc. In the same way it is possible to say "That
Newton was a great genius cannot be denied," but if we do not want to place
the clause with that first we have to say "It cannot be denied that Newton
was a great genius."  In these sentences it represents the following
infinitive construction or clause, very much as in "He is a great scoundrel,
that husband of hers" he represents the words that husband of hers.  Cf. the
colloquial: "It is perfectly wonderful the way in which he remembers things."

The rules for the use of the auxiliary do in interrogative sentences are
to be explained in a similar way. The universal tendency is towards having
the word-order Subject Verb, but there is a conflicting tendency to express
a question by means of the inverted order Verb Subject, as in the obsolete
"writes he' " (cf. German "Schreibt er?" and French "Ecrit-il?").  Now many
interrogative sentences had the word-order Auxiliary Subject Verb (" Can he
write ~.. "Will he write? " "Has he written," etc.), in which the really
significant verb eame after the subject just as in ordinary affirmative
sentences: through the creation of the compromise form "does he write?" the
two conflicting tendencies were reconciled: from a formal point of view the
verb, though an empty one, preceded the subject to indioate the question,
and from another point of view the subject preceded the real verb. But no
auxiliary is required when the sentence has an interrogative pronoun as
subject ("Who writes?") because the interrogatory pronoun is naturally put
first, and so the sentence without any does conforms already to the
universal pattern.

Anakoluthia : breaking off a sentence


[this is one of the main difficulties of psycholinguistics - how exactly is
the sentence produced?  Is it a matter of subconscious habit, or is it more
deliberative?
Anyone who will listen oarefully to ordinary conversation will come across
abundant evidence of the way in which sentenoes are bullt up gradually by
the speaker, who will often in the course of the same sentence modify his
original plan of presenting his ideas, hesitate, break off, and shunt on to
a different track. In
written and printed language this phenomenon, anakoluthia, is of
course much rarer than in speech, though instanoes are well known
to scholars.  [cites passage from King Lear earliest quarto edition, dropped
in Folio - "like a better way" which scholars have struggled over.  Suggests
that it should be read as a "her smiles and tears
Were like - [a pause here, followed by an improved thought] -a better way:
[and then the colourful description of Cordelia..] p.28-29

anakoluthia: after starting a sentence, re-considers the content and
	continues in a manner inconsistent with the start
(not in OED, but in this sense in german wikipedia Anakoluth)

My chief object in writing this chapter has been to make the reader rea1ize
that language is not just dictionaries and the usual grammars ...  but a set
of habits, of habitual actions, and that each word and each sentence spoken
is a complex action on the part of the speaker.

1n each instance, apart from mere formulas, the speaker has to turn these
habits to meet a new situation, to express what has not been expressed
previously - therefore he cannot be a mere slave to habits but has to vary
them to suit varying needs and this in course of time may lead to new turns
and new habits; in other words, to new grammatical forms and usages.

Grammar thus becomes a part of linguistic psychology or psychological
linguistics...

Chapter II: Systematic Grammar


two ways of treating linguistic phenomena: descriptive and the
historical.

Corresponds to what in physics are called statics and dynamics and differ in
that the one views phenomena as being in equilibrium, and the other views
them as being in motion.

It is the pride of the linguistic science of the last hundred years or so
that it has superseded older methods by historical grammar, in which
phenomena are not only described, but explained, and it cannot be denied that
the new point of view, by showing the inter-connexion of grammatical
phenomena previously isolated, has obtained many new and important results.

We can explain many irregularities, but to the speakers of our modern
language they are just as irregular as if their origin had not been made
clear to us.  The distinction between regular and irregular always must be
important to the psychological life of language, for regular forms are those
which speakers use as the basis of new formations, and irregular forms are
those which they will often tend to replace by new forms created on the
principle of analogy.

Grammar vs Dictionary : general vs specific


Grammar deals with the general facts of language, and lexicology with special
facts (cf. Sweet, CP 31). That cat denotes that particular animal is a
special fact which concerns that word alone, but the formation of the plural
by adding the sound -s is a general fact because it concerns a great many
other words as well: rats, hats, works, books, caps, chiefs, etc. 82

... such facts as the formation of ordinals by means of the ending -th and of
20, 30, etc., by means of -ty unquestionably belong to the province of
grammar. p.32


What categories to recognize in a grammar?


The prinoiple here advocated. is that we should recognize in the syntax of
any language only such categories as have found in that language formal
expression, but it will be remembered that "form" is taken in a very wide
sense, including form-words and word-position. In thus making form the
supreme criterion one should beware, however, of a mistaken notion whioh
might appear to be the natural outcome of the same principle. We say one
sheep, many sheep: are we then to say that sheep is not a singular in the
first phrase, and not a plural in the second, because it has the same form,
and that this form. is rather to be caJIed ' common number' or 'no-number' or
something equivalent?

[Similarly] 
	"I cut my finger every day"  : is cut in present tense?
	"I cut my finger yesterday"  : is cut past tense (preterit)?

Further, if we compare "our king's love for his subjects" and "our 
kings love their subjects," we see that the two forms are the same (apart
from the purely conventional distinction made in writing, but not in
speaking, by means of the apostrophe), and a strict formalist thus would not
be entitled to state anything with regard to the case and number of
kings. And what about love?  There is nothing in the form to show us that
it is a substantive in the singular in one phrase and. a verb in the plural
in the other, and we should have to invent a separate name for the strange
category thus created.

The true moral to be drawn from such examples is, however, I think, that it
is wrong to treat each separate linguistic item on its own merits; we should
rather look at the language as a whole.  Sheep in many sheep is a plural,
because in many lambs and hundreds of other similar cases the English
language recognIzes a plural in its substantives; cut in one sentence is in
the present and in the other in the past tense, because a difference at once
arises if we substitute he for _I_ (he cuts, he cut), or another verb for
cut (I tear, I tore)... [Similarly for kings and love]. 

Surface form needs to be evaluated with reference to context

In other words, while we should be careful to keep out of the grammar of any
language such distinctions or categories as are found in other languages, but
are not formally expressed in the language in question, we should be no less
averse to deny in a particular case the existence of distinctions
elsewhere made in the same Ianguage, because they happen there to have no
outward sign. 51

The principle laid down in the last few paragraphs is not unfrequently sinned
against in grammatical literature.  Many writers will discourse on the
faclility with which English can turn substantives into verbs, and vice
versa-but English never confounds the two classes of words, even if it uses
the same form now as a substantive, and now as a verb: a finger and a
find are substantives, and finger and find in you finger this and find
that are verbs, in flexion and in function and everything.  An annotator on
the passage in Hamlet, where the ghost is said to go "slow and stately" says
with regard to slow; "Adjectives are often used for adverbs " - no, slow
really is an adverb, just as long in "he stayed long" is an adverb, even if
the form is the same as in "a long stay," where it is an adjective.

[the nature of a surface form word needs to be considered with respect to
its companions - what are its nearest neighbours?]
 

bookexcerptise is maintained by a small group of editors. get in touch with us!
bookexcerptise [at] gmail [] com.

This review by Amit Mukerjee was last updated on : 2015 Dec 18