book excerptise:   a book unexamined is wasting trees

From Stimulus to Science

Willard Van Orman Quine

Quine, Willard Van Orman;

From Stimulus to Science

Harvard University Press, 1995, 114 pages  [gbook]

ISBN 0674326350, 9780674326354

topics: |  philosophy | science | history |

History of philosophy of science


    We and other animals notice what goes on around us.  This helps us by
suggesting what we might expect and even how to prevent it, and thus fosters
survival.  However, the expedient works only imperfectly. There are
surprises, and they are unsettling.  How can we tell when we are right? We
are faced with the problem of error.

    These are worries about our knowledge of the external world.  To deal
with them we have had to turn inward and seek knowledge of knowledge.  "Know
thyself": the injunction is attributed to Socrates and even to Thales,
purportedly the father of philosophy.

    Thales and his successors were concerned not only with man and his
errors; they speculated on the cosmos.  But anxiety over the problem of error
continued through Greek antiquity.  The paradoxes of Zeno and Eubulides were
calculated to show the limitations of our judgment, as were the sophistries
of the Sophists.  The Skeptics took the melancholy conclusions to heart. 1

Ways of knowing: Plato / Aristotle

    How do we know things?  Plato held that we do so by apprehending
ideas-really forms, as we would say-that are the essences of things.  He
thought we were born knowing these forms and their interrelations in a
blurred way, and that they could be brought into focus by Socratic dialogue.
It seems from one of the dialogues, the Meno, that Plato arrived at this
theory by thinking about mathematical argumentation from self-evident truths.
Somehow, though, he accommodated observation too.  "Save the appearances," he
wrote.

    Aristotle tried to shore up the ways of knowing.  He formalized the
syllogism.  Knowledge itself, however, outpaced knowledge about knowledge.
Natural history throve in Aristotle's hands, and mathematics in those of
Eudoxus and Euclid.  Eratosthenes even calculated the size of the earth,
nearly enough.

    But darkness descended, and mists of myth and mysticism settled in for a
thousand years.  Ways of knowing dwindled to one: higher authority. Remnants
from Aristotle were deemed authoritative, but now had he known? Infinite
regress loomed.

    The problem was shelved by positing supernatural revelation.  This
position was a stubborn one, for we cannot then question divine revelation
without begging the question.

    [NOTE: posit ==> position - etymology L. positus, pp. of ponere, "put,
   place", noun 1703 (dance steps), 1883 (sexual intercourse), back to verb
   in 1817 "to put in a given position"]

Experimentalism: The two Bacons

Roger Bacon did beg it, along about 1290, by espousing observation and
experiment.  Two and a half centuries later, Copernicus made the
breakthrough that put science unmistakably on the upward track.  For
fourteen centuries straggling astronomers has struggled with Ptolemaic
epicycles to systematize an astronomy centered on the earth; but at
last Copernicus put our planet in its place and set it moving.

    Thus inspired, Francis Bacon took up the old question of the ways of
knowing.  The spirit of Roger Bacon was reawakened, but now with more
substance and sophistication, the wisdom of hindsight.  Science had broken
through, though traditionalists tried to restrain it.  A full century after
Copernicus, the clergy prosecuted Galileo for embracing the Copernican
heresy.  One thinks of the creationists today, one hundred thirty years after
Darwin's Origin of Species.

[p.3]
Despite obstructions, science attained full flower fifty years after
Galileo's work.  It flowered in Newton's Philosophiae Naturalis
Principia Mathematica (1687).

The materialism of Hobbes: Physicalist beginnings

    In the more broadly philosophical arena, meanwhile, there was Thomas
Hobbes.  He was twenty-four years younger than Galileo, and was inspired by
Galileo's strides.  Hobbes professed utter materialism, indeed mechanism,
like Democritus two thousand years before: there is nothing but matter in
motion.  Thought is motion in the brain.


Hobbes's view of knowledge was strikingly modern.  Our sensations are
the effects upon us of the otherwise unknowable material world.  It is
on these that we base our ideas about the world, and we have nothing
further to go on but the meshing of the ideas.

    Hobbes uses the word 'idea' in its modern sense, to mean something like a
thought or a concept.  He was the first to do so in English, according to the
Oxford English Dictionary.  It was an odd reversal of Plato's usage.  For
Plato ideas or forms had been reality par excellence; things of the material
world were their imperfect counterfeits.  For Hobbes and us, ideas are rather
man's faltering attempt to encompass material reality.

    [ETYMOLOGY "Idea":: 1430, "figure, image, symbol," from L. idea "idea,"
    and in Platonic philosophy "archetype," from Gk. idea "ideal
    prototype," lit. "look, form," from idein "to see."  Sense of "result
    of thinking" first recorded 1645.  Archetype = "original model",
    original, that which is real outside.  Link to "idein", to see. ]

Descartes: Do we know?


    Rene Descartes was Hobbes's junior by eight years.  He was a dualist: he
recognized both mind and matter.  Descartes came to grips, more vigorously
than Hobbes or Bacon, with the question of how we know.  In his famous
thought experiment he proceeded from scratch.  He tried doubting everything,
but found that he could not doubt that he was doubting.  He concluded that he
existed, as a mind.  Then he proceeded to the existence of God.  Sensing more
treacherous ground there, he offered four proofs.  The existence of matter
then came easily: we have a clear and distinct idea of matter, and since God
is by definition good, he would not give us a clear and distinct but false
idea.

    Such, roughly stated, was Descartes's theory of how we know.  Clear and
distinct ideas are knowledge, and God given; confused ideas are not.  There
are echoes here of Plato's doctrine on innate knowledge and reminiscence, and
of the Hebrew and Christian doctrine of divine revelation.  But the Platonic
bit may have been a case of parallel inspiration rather than heritage.
Plato's view was evidently inspired by mathematics, and Descartes was a
mathematician.

Locke: Knowledge from sense impressions

    In the five-year period 1646-1650 five neoclassical philosophers were
alive: Hobbes, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Locke.  In the history of
epistemology the next significant figure after Descartes is John Locke.

    Locke shunned Descartes's theological epistemology.  Like Hobbes, he saw
knowledge in the coherence of ideas.  He accepted the material world as real,
but as known only tentatively by conjecture from ideas.  Sense impressions,
caused by the material world, implant our simple ideas; we build or abstract
all other ideas from these.  Contrary to Descartes, Locke repudiated innate
ideas.  He subscribed to the empiricist manifesto: nihil in mente quod non
prius in sensu.
[There is nothing in the mind that isn't there (earlier??) in the senses]

    Locke did not explain how to form complex ideas of material objects, real
or fictitious, on the basis of simple sense impressions.  He wrote of the
association of ideas by contiguity, succession, and resemblance, but this is
the barest beginning of what goes into the most primitive report on the
material world around us.  What of our identification of an intermittently
observed body as the same body?  An identical body can look different over
time, and different bodies can look alike.  Much remained to be explained.

Berkeley and God

[p.5]
Bishop George Berkeley, fifty years younger than Locke, saw no cogency
in Hobbes's or Locke's conjecture of a material world.  Nothing
exists, Berkeley held, but what is directly perceived.  Nothing,
therefore, but sensory patterns, or occurrences of sensory patterns?
No, he was more generous than that.  He admitted souls; we perceive
ours.  And somehow he admitted God.  This done, Berkeley provides for
the persistence of things irrespective of whether or when they are
perceived by man or beast; for they remain faithfully perceived by
God.  Berkeley's disavowal of matter, then, would seem to be a matter
of words.

Hume: Empiricism

    David Hume, twenty-six years Berkeley's junior, acquiesced rather in the
conclusion that there simply is no evidence for the continued existence of an
object between one occasion and another of our perceiving it.  The very
identification of it as the same object, on the one occasion and the other,
is in his view a confusion of identity with similarity.

    Locke, Berkeley, and Hume were the classic British empiricists, and their
pertinent writings appeared in the years 1690-1757.  All three agreed that
our lore about the world is a fabric of ideas based on sense impressions.
Regarding the structured details of the fabric and its fabrication, all three
were at a loss for the rudiments of an account.  The idea is a frail reed.

    As Wittgenstein observed, even a simple sense quality is elusive unless
braced by public language.  An individual might reckon many sensory events as
recurrences of one quality on the strength of resemblance of each to the
next, despite a substantial accumulation of slight differences.  Public
naming and monitoring are what arrest such drift.  Random deviations of
individual speakers are held within bounds by the speakers' communicating
with one another.  Public words anchor ideas.  Irresponsible appeal to the
idea is still our popular usage.  The purpose of language is said to be the
communication of ideas.

    Irresponsible appeal to the idea is still our popular usage.  The purpose
of language is said to be the communication of ideas.  We learn a word from
our elders by associating it with the same idea, and we use it in the
communication of ideas.  How do we know that the words we use to express our
ideas are conjuring up the same ideas in the minds of our listeners? Words
and observable behavior are all we have to go on, and the idea provides only
the illusion of an explanation.

Tooke: how ideas may be composed

John Horne Tooke urged the point in 1786, ten years after Hume's death.
	I only desire you to read [Locke's] essay over again with
	attention to see whether all that its immortal author has
	justly concluded will not hold equally true and clear, if you
	substitute the composition, of terms wherever he has supposed
	a composition of ideas . . . The greatest part of Mr. Locke's
	essay, that is, all which relates to what he calls the
	abstraction, complexity, generalization, etc., of ideas, does
	indeed merely concern language. (Pp. 37-38)

    Tooke was a kindred spirit of his remote predecessor William of Ockham
and other medieval nominalists, who had dismissed abstract objects as flatus
vocis, vocal breeze.  Tooke's was a major step toward what Richard Rorty has
called the linguistic turn.  If there is sense to be made for the compounding
of ideas, clearer sense can be made of the compounding of language.  Words,
unlike ideas, are out where we can see what we are doing.

Jeremy Bentham's Holism: words are understood in terms of sentences

    Much further freedom in the constructing of ideas -- or, now, terms --
was achieved by Jeremy Bentham a few years later in his theory of fictions.
He observed that to explain a term we do not need to compose a synonymous
phrase.  We need only explain all sentences in which we propose to use the
term.  It is what is now called contextual definition.  Bentham's motive was
ontological: he wanted to be able to introduce one or another useful term
without being charged with assuming some controversial object for it to
designate, or objects for it do denote.  The seeming object or objects could
in this way be dismissed as innocent fictions.

Holistic thought in India

[p.7]
In India there has been debate since the seventh century over whether
sentences or words are the primary vehicles of meaning.  Since the
lexicon or Wortschatz is finite whereas the realm of admissible
sentences, the Satzschatz, is boundless, a systematic guide to a
language must consist of a dictionary of words and a grammar for
building sentences from them.  The words, on the other hand, will
mostly be explained in the dictionary by their use in illustrative
sentences.  The goal of the whole enterprise is to inculcate facility
in understanding and producing correct and useful sentences.

    In learning our native language we zigzag similarly.  We learn a simple
sentence as a whole, and then we project a component word of it by analogy
into the construction of another sentence.  Nowadays an appreciation of
contextual definition - Bentham's insight - has lent support to the view of
sentences as the primary vehicles of meaning.  It is a view that Gottlieb
Frege vigorously espoused a century after Bentham.

	[George Boole's contextual definition of OPERATORS in differential
	calculus - e.g. d/dx can stand for an operator that cannot stand
	alone without the f(x).  Boole's innovation was to take an expression
	such as d2/dx2 f(x,y,z) + d/dy2... ] in the compact fashion (d2/dx2 +
	d2/dy2 + d2/dz2) f(x,y,z), and then to manipulate it as if it stood
	for a sum of three genuine quantities multiplied into f(x,y,z).

Russell's Singular description

It was this very example that inspired [PM v.1 p.66] Bertrand
Russell's familiar contextual definition of the singular description
(ix)Fx:

	   G(ix)Fx for (Ey)(Gy ^ Vx(x=y EQ Fx))

    [The singular description is ] one of the many deft contributions of
Whitehead and Russell's three forbidding volumes of Principia Mathematica,
which appeared in 1910-13.  Their heroic project was to clarify the whole
intricate structure of classical mathematics by deriving its principal
concepts, step by step and definition after definition, from a slender basis
of clear and simple primitive terms, and deriving its principal laws pari
passu from a few postulates.  . . .  The economical foundation achieved in
Principia, and further reduced by subsequent logicians [Frege/Peirce/Peano],
now comprises only the truth functions and quantification of elementary logic
plus the two-place predicate \epsilon of class membership.  The whole
conceptual scheme of classical mathematics boils down to just that.

    . . . The conclusion [Whitehead and Russell and Frege before them] drew
was that mathematics was translatable into pure logic. They counted
membership as logic.  So mathematical truth is logical truth, and hence all
of it must be deducible from self-evident logical truths. This is wrong, as
transpires in part from Kurt Godel's paper of 1931 and in part from findings
by Russell himself in 1902.

    Buoyed by their achievement, Russell reflected in 1914 on realizing the
dream of empiricist epistemologists: the explicit construction of the
external world, or a reasonable facsimile, from sense impressions, hence from
simple ideas.  He adumbrated it in Our Knowledge of the External World, and a
dozen years later Rudolf Canap was undertaking to carry it out.  Carnap's
effort found expression in Der logische Aufbau der Welt (1928). [10]

Carnap's Aufbau: From sensation to meaning

    Carnap's building blocks were to be sensory elements, as in the
constructions dreamed of by the old British empiricists.  But what sensory
elements?  Atomic sense data?  The Gestalt psychologists claimed that we are
first aware of various organized wholes, and then we abstract the atoms.
Carnap circumvented that issue by settling for unorganized global
experiences.  Each of his elements was the individual's total experience at
the moment, or perhaps during the specious present.  These global units he
called elementary experiences.

    Carnap's basic relation between elementary experiences was {\it
remembering as similar}.  I shall call it R.  One elementary
experience, x, bears R to another, y, if x includes a memory of y as
partially resembing x. [p.10]

    Here, as in Principia Mathematica, economy was part of the game.  Carnap
allowed himself free use of logic and mathematics, and in addition just one
two-place predicate, the one I am calling R.  He does not need to assume a
further predicate to denote the elementary experiences, for he can define it:
an elementary experience is anything that bears R to anything, or to which
anything bears R.  This can be expressed in terms of R and logic.  Next he
defines part similarity of elementary experiences: it holds if one of them
bears R to the other, forward or backward.  This definition would seem to
deliver not just "part similar", but "remembered as part similar"; but let us
pass over that.

    By a more subtle definition Carnap introduces what he calls similarity
circles.  A similarity circle is any largest class of elementary experiences
each of which is part similar to each [every one].  It is the largest in the
sense that no elementary experience outside the class is similar to every
member. [p.11]

    This brings him to the point where he can define the notion of a sense
quality.  This definition well displays Carnap's ingenuity.  He sets his
sights on quality classes, a quality class is the class of all elementary
experiences that represent a given quality.  All the elementary experiences
in a quality class are part-similar, by virtue of sharing the quality.  Still
the class will be narrower than a similarity circle, for the members of a
similarity circle need not all share any one quality.  But Carnap argues that
the quality class will always be the common part of all the similarity
circles that it overlaps by more than half.  This works out, he argues, if
experience is reasonably varied and random.

Foundation: Similarity of qualities

    Similarity of qualities is based on part-similarity of elementary
experiences (share one quality) ==> manages to define the five senses: sight,
smell, taste, hearing, and touch.  Each sense is the largest class of
qualities that are connected to each other by similarity.  . . .  each of the
five senses can be singled out by dimensionality; for, Carnap points out,
each has a different number of dimensions.  Sight for instance, has five: the
two spatial dimensions and the three dimensions of color.  Dimension itself
is definable mathematically, hence ultimately by logic and membership.  . . .

    [As a first step in constructing a full system of physical reality from
this sensory foundation, he envisaged] a projection of visual qualities of
our two-dimensional visual field into three-dimensional space.  Imagine lines
projected outward from all points in the rounded front of the subject's eye.
Each line is perpendicular to its immediate neighbourhood on that rounded
surface.  Each is the subject's line of sight from that point on the eye, and
thus corresponds to a point in the subject's visual field.  The colour of
that point in the visual field is to be assigned to a point on that line of
sight, out in three-dimensional space.  Colors are to be assigned in this way
to all lines of sight, one color to each.  The remaining question is, how far
out on each line?  [p.12]


    These distances are to be adjusted, Carnap answers, so as to minimize the
variegation of colors in the resulting three-dimensional space.  And not only
that, we must try also to minimize or retard the variegation of color over
time at each point, thus going back and readjusting earlier assignments in
the light of later input.  In short, we are to so assign colors to points in
space-time as to make for the drabbest and slowest possible world.  A law of
least action gets built into our very standard of what to count as ral.  This
was a deep insight of Carnap's.  It is a stick-figure caricature of what the
scientist actually does, early and late, in devising theories.  It is the
scientist's quest of the simplest solution.  [p.13]

    For the subsequent construction of the physical world, one could not hope
to proceed purely by definition; for minimization requires us to go back and
reconsider past spatial allocations of qualities in the light of later
ones. [Why not a 4D incremental algorithm?]

Naturalism (Chapter 2)


    The idea of a self-sufficient sensory language as a foundation for
science loses its lustre when we reflect that systematization of our sensory
intake is the very business that science itself is engaged in.  The memories
that link our past experiences with present ones and induce our expectations
are themselves mostly memories not of sensory intake but of things and events
in the physical world.  This led Otto Neurath, Carnap's colleague in Vienna,
to persuade Carnap to give up his methodological phenomenalism in favour of
physicalism.

A physicalist approach to the Carnapian enterprise

    [Carnap's "rational reconstruction" embraces] a Cartesian dualism of mind
and body, if not indeed a mentalistic monism.  Physicalism, on the other
hand, is materialism, bluntly monistic except for the abstract objects of
mathematics.

    [Carnap refused to pursue] the pragmatic alternative of a physically
based constitution system for science. He refused for decades to permit an
English edition of the Aufbau.  [Quine sets out to pursue that physicalist
alternative.]  [16]

    Two directions suggest themselves. One, aimed solely at conceptual
economy and clarity is pretty much what physicists at the theoretical pole
have long been up to, though the logician might lend a welcome hand in the
trimming and polishing before the final miniaturized model is cast in bronze.

    The other direction, more analogous to Carnap's Aufbau, is what I think
of as NATURALISM.  It is rational reconstruction of the individual's and/or
the race's actual acquisition of a responsible theory of the external world.
[Q. What is "responsible"? ] It would address the question how we, physical
denizens of the physical world, can have projected our scientific theory of
that whole world from our meager contacts with it: from the mere impacts of
rays and particles on our surfaces and a few odds and ends such as the strain
of walking uphill.

	[Q. What of deliberately constructed apparatus / experiments leading
	 to observations in science]

GLOBAL STIMULUS: Carnap's ground elements were his elementary
experiences; each was the subject's total sensory experience during
some moment, or specious present.  Global Stimulus is its physical
analogue, the class of all sensory receptors triggered at that moment,
or, better, the temporally ordered class of receptors triggered during
that specious present.  [But what are the bounds in time for this
"temporally ordering", or for the "specious present"?]

    "let me drop the memory factor here" [But then, how to compare temporally
separated stimuli? How to abstract incrementally from stimuli?]

Similarity of Sensation

    [Quine builds up the distinction between external phenomena and the
    signals at the nerve endings, called receptors.  Perceptual similarity
    may not result in receptual similarity, but can be measured by looking
    at the sensory-action map.  If similar receptory signals A and B result
    in opposite rewards, then whether C is more similar to A or B can be
    tested by seeing if the reaction to C is that of A or that of B.]

RECEPTUAL SIMILARITY: Two global stimuli are more or less similar
according as they comprise more or less the same nerve endings in the
same order.

PERCEPTUAL SIMILARITY: A and B are receptually similar signals, but
the same action in A gets a reward and in B a penalty.  Now when
encountering stimulus C, if the reaction is the same action as in A it
means C is more similar to A than to B. [18]

   (perceptual similarity is encoded by models of memory - see
    Missing Moment: How the Unconscious Shapes Modern Science, chapter 3.)

[May be asymmetric due to the temporal recency of the experience of B].
EXAMPLE: Seeing a rectangle from different perspectives - different
receptual similarity but high perceptual sim - "intrinsic propensity
to associate perspectives" [Seems unlikely?] [19]

SALIENCE: Global stimuli are excessive; need to focus on only the
salient ones.  May be receptually dissimlar but perc
similar.  Salience refers to those receptors within a g.s. that are
shared with other perc similar g.s..  Thus, g.s. are perceptually
similar by virtue of the shared salience.  The inversion [??] is in
the spirit of Carnap's constructions.

Salience is the operative factor for "ostensive" definition.
[ostensive = manifest; etym from L. ostendere, to show. WN: manifestly
	   demonstrative?
ostension = seeing?]

[NOTE: Idea of salience is similar to what Langacker has called
symbolic unit - how the semantic unit is related to a phonological
unit.  The semantic unit requires reification - coming up next.  But
is it also possible without reification?  "Cold", "Thunder"? ]

    I have come this far in my physical mimicry of phenomenalistic
epistemology without invading the percipient organisms more deeply than his
sensory receptors.  All that has mattered is the individual's distinctive
responses to their activation.  I shall not have to invade him more deeply,
despite the illuminating progress of psychoneurology.

Animal communication units

[Apes, birds, humans share information through cries or calls] Apes have
a repertoire of distinct signals for distinct purposes.  One signal warns the
fellow apes of the approach of a lion or leopard, another warns of an eagle,
another perhaps the sighting of some fruit trees while the troop is ranging
through the forest.  Each member of the tribe is disposed to broadcast the
appropriate signal on experiencing a certain range of perceptually similar
global stimulations, and to react with appropriate motor behaviour on hearing
the signal.

[	Thomas Struhsaker reported in 1967 that vervets gave distinct alarm
	calls in response to spotting three predators (leopards, eagles,
	and snakes), and the listeners would appropriately in each case.
	The calls appear to function as "representational, or
	semantic, signals" (125).
	    "When one vervet hears another give an eagle alarm call, the
	listener responds as if it had seen the eagle itself. This
	behavior suggests that in the monkey's mind the call "stands for"
	or "conjures up images of" an avian predator even when the monkey
	has not yet see the eagle" (125). In the language of memory,
	Seyfarth and Cheney (1992) is making the proposition that
	vervets have evolved explicit categorical (semantic) recall ...
	But [the main difference with humans is that] they do not
	seem to recognize mental states in others.
	Seyfarth and Cheney, Scientific American, December 1992. ]

Private and public language


    There is a puzzle here.  Global stimuli are private: each is a
temporally ordered set of one indivisual's receptors.  Their perceptual
similarity, in part innate and in part molded by experience, is private as
well.  Whence then this coordination of behaviours across the tribe? It
requires that if two individuals jointly witness one scene, and
subsequently jointly witness another scene, and the one witness's g.s's on
two occasions qualify for him as perceptually similar, usually the other
witness's gs's will also qualify thus. [20]

    So we see a pre-established harmony of perceptual similarity standards.
... This public harmony of private standards is accounted for by natural
selection.  The indiv's standards of percep similarity are inculcated by
natural selection and due to shared ancestry and shared environment, will
tend to harmonize across the tribe.  There is also the discipline imposed by
the vocal signals themselves, and later, language: random deviations among
indiv's get canceled out by their hearing the signals from each other. [21]

Issues with Reification


A. Utterances reflect reified concepts - and may result in reification
   across the language group.
B. Phonological standardization occurs when utterances are deemed
   non-meaningful (or same as other signs, or overly distinct) by
   others, focusing attention on the phonemic boundaries.
C. Even if the signals change as a whole in the group (due to social
   power structures etc, these changes would also propagate and
   stabilize
D. Perceptual similarity refers to the stimulus-action map.  This
   requires that signals reflect the same USAGE patterns. ]

Observation Sentences


human counterparts of bird-calls and apes' cries...  "It's raining",
"It's cold", "Dog!" They are occasion sentences - true on some
occasions.  They report intersubjectively observable situations,
observable outright.

    The pertinent language community is a parameter that we may take more
broadly or narrowly according to the purpose of our study.  VAGUENESS: What
does "outright" mean? how many seconds of reflection?

    Take the "Swan!" or "Lo, a swan': would our speaker affirm it of a black
one?  [Australian swans are black] - gradations...

    Within the individual the observation is keyed to a range of perc similar
g.stimuli - it is due to the pre-established harmony that they qualify as
observation sentences across the community.

    Observation sentences are not only the prehuman counterparts of language,
but they are also its inception as with the recruitment of each new child
into the language community.  Some o.s's such as "Milk!" or "Dog!" are what
we in our sophistication see as terms denoting things, but to the child,
innocent at first of any thought of reification and reference, they are on
par with "It's cold" and "It's raining": just things to say in distinctive
circumstances.  [22]

[NOTE: This is an assumption reiterated through the book - but psychological
data on rigid objects would appear to indicate that perceptually,
there is evidence for reification well before observational sentences
appear.  The low probability of coherent visual flow associated with
coherent objects make them perceptually similar much before they are
linguistically formed.]

    The child is innately more agile at learning new observation sentences by
ostension, and beyond this soon learns connectives by which to compound new
observation sentences from old ones.  'Not' and 'and' come to mind. A
negative obsvn s, 'Not p' is probably learned when the child's mentor utters
it as a correction to the child's utterance of obsvn s 'p'.  The connective
'and' is painlessly acquired amounting as it does to the merest punctuation
between affirmations.

    [All this can be tricky.  Consider: "Walk out of that crib again and I
will tie up your hands." Necessary to assume that the caretaker is
deliberately using a simpler form of language, reflecting more standard
usages of these connectives, and hence that the caretaker is aware of the
centers for these semantic prototypes.  ]

    On learning 'not' and 'and' the child internalizes a bit of logic, for to
affirm 'p and not p' is to have mislearned one or both particles.

    The child masters further connectives : above, beneath, before, after,
in, beside [NOTE: all are spatial.  IDEA**: USE next quottation in Spatial
learning work. ]

    Perhaps the child learns such a connective by learning a compound obsvn
sentence outright as a whole by direct ostension. Then having learned also
each of the components independently, he catches on to the trick and proceeds
to apply the connective by analogy to other pairs. [24]

From observation to grammar

    One of these primitive grammatical constructions in particular si
significant as a first step toward reification of bodies.  Applied to simple
observation sentences 'Black' or 'that's black' or 'Dog', it forms the
compound 'black dog' or 'that dog is black' - as an observation sentence the
compound can be phrased either way, since terms are not yet recognized as
denoting.  I call this primitive grammatical construction "observational
predication", in anticipation of the mature predication into which it will
evolve.

Observational Predication is quite a different matter from mere
conjunction.  The conjunction describes any scene in which black and dog
are salient, whereas 'black dog' requires that they be situated
together, the black patch engulfing the canine patch.  The predication
expresses the compact clustering of visual qualities that is
characteristic of a body.

    Bodies are our first reifications: the first objects to be taken as
objects.  It is in analogy to them that all further positing of objects takes
place... typically it contrasts with its visual surroundings in color and in
movement or parallax, and typically it is fairly chunky and compact.  If we
make contact, it resists pressure.  These traits distinguish it from [mere
sensations] - the colour of the evening sky, the feel of a cool breeze, [the
sound of an aria] or other details of the passing show. The mode of
compounding observation sentences that I have called predication, then, is a
step towards reification of bodies, in its stress on spatial clustering.
However, I hold that at this point reification is not yet achieved.
[NOTE: THIS last may prove to be incorrect.  Given the perceptual
salience of a coherently moving black blob, which subsequently is
identified with "dog", the co-visuality of black and dog would be more
salient and therefore more likely to be the interpretation of "black
dog" even if the utterance were "black and dog". ]

Observation Categoricals


Meanwhile I turn to what I picture as the first step beyond ordinary
observation sentences: namely a generalize expression of expectation.
It is a way of joining two obsvn s's A and B to express the general
expectation that whenever A holds, B will be fulfilled as well.  "When
it snows, it's cold"; "Where there is smoke, there's fire", "When the
sun rises, birds sing".

    The leap from observation sentences to observation categoricals to is a
giant one, for o categoricals are the direct expression of inductive
expectation, which underlies all learning.  O c's bring us vicarious
habituation, vicarious induction.  One gets the benefit of generalized
expectations built up over the years by some veteran observer or even by that
veteran's own informant long dead.  Observation categoricals can be handed
down. 25

    Even at this stage there is no denotation, no reference.  The child's
observation sentences 'Mama' and 'Doggy; register repeatable features of the
passing show, on a par with 'Cold' and 'Thunder'.  Nevertheless we have a
[modest] sketch of a causal chain from the imprint of rays and particles on
our receptors to a rudimentary theory of the external world.

    Observation categoricals are indeed a [miniature] scientific theory of
the world, complete with empirical checkpoints subject to the experimental
method.  ... by waiting for an occasion where the first component of
categorical is fulfilled, or even by bringing about its fulfillment, and
watching ...  [26]


to contribute some excerpts from your favourite book to book excerptise. send us a plain text file with page-numbered extracts from your favourite book. You can preface your extracts with a short review.
email to (bookexcerptise [at] gmail [dot] com).

We reply to all feedback!



bookexcerptise is maintained by a small group of editors. get in touch with us! bookexcerptise [at] gmail [dot] .com.

This article last updated on : 2014 Nov 14