Millikan, Ruth Garrett;
Language: A Biological Model
Oxford University Press, 2005, 228 pages [gbook]
ISBN 0199284776, 9780199284771
topics: | philosophy | linguistics | linguistics
Ten essays that have appeared in various journals and books. Much of the work deals with the notion of convention in language, but more generally about the prescriptive normative rules, the partial regularities underlying language.
The first chapter analyzes the notion of convention, and establishes some conditions for "convention" to hold - such as reproducibility - However, I found the chapter on Why (most) kinds are not classes, where she develops the notion of historical continuity, or eternal essence that defines a category, as opposed to any notion of present-day similarity etc - this turns out to be rather similar to the biological norms used to define a species (which turn out to be historical as well). Some more details of the argument.
Much of this essay is an analysis of the process of convention, and draws heavily on the work of Lewis; particularly "Convention: A Philosophical Study" (1969), based on his phd, at the start of which he says: "It is a platitude that language is ruled by convention", and proceeds to to give us 'an analysis of convention in its full genearlity, including tacit convention not created by agreement. In this work, Lewis uses concepts of game theory to analyze the nature of social conventions, and claims that [wiki:]
social conventions, such as the convention that one is driving on the right (not on the left), the convention that the original caller will re-call if a phone conversation is interrupted, etc., are solutions to so-called "'co-ordination problems'". Co-ordination problems were at the time of Lewis's book a much under-discussed kind of game-theoretical problem; most of the game-theoretical discussion had circulated around problems where the participants are in conflict, such as the prisoner's dilemma. [Of course, these solutions also exhibit Nash equilibrium properties - AM]
This lays out an approach for tackling these based on game-theoretic notions. Lewis' analysis is very complex, calling for a number of factors, e.g. in a driving context, both agents must be aware of the keep-to-the-left rule, and both must know that the other knows that she knows that the other knows etc. Millikan tries to simplify these situations where conventions arise in terms of two requirements - that it should be possible to imitate it (reproduce) in a hand-me-down manner; and that this is how it "has been done" (weight of precedent). In addition she outlines several types of coordination situation - e.g. the leader-follower where one person follows the cues of the other,
[ RM uses the word "reproduce" or "handed-down", but imitative maybe clearer, or does this alter RM's point altogether? ] considers conventions like "shirt-buttoning" - if it is efficient to button it from top downwards, such behaviour may have been independently discovered by a population, but would not be "handed-down" hence it would not be conventional. Thus to be conventional, a behaviour must be imitated. Several ways: Conventions may reproduce by being told. An example of a 2-step conventional pattern reproducing by telling arises when Johnny's mother tells him that he is to put his letter in the mailbox and put up the flag. The result is that he reproduces the first part of a conventional pattern of activity, the second part of which will be reproduced by the mailman, who, on seeing the flag, will pick up the contents of the mailbox, and then put the flag down. Counterpart reproduction: Arises when a bolt and a nut are to have the same gauge. e.g. positions assumed by men and women in traditional ballroom dancing. "Copies of copies may drift away, but the need to fit counterparts retards drift." 5 Unconscious reproduction: e.g. interpersonal distance - if too small, one moves back, but it may be reinforced by the need not to circumambulate around the room.
Patterns are conventional only if there are other patterns that could have been substituted, given other historical accidents. Quotes bird songs as being non-conventional but arbitrary. [but this is perhaps belied by other evidence, see, e.g. Meredith West's study of cowbird song across different ecotopes in the continental USA: NC males can learn TX songs, IN males can learn SD, can become bilingual - NC males could learn TX song from TX females who can't themselves sing it... so the males can adapt to a contingency. But is it the females here then who become "standard-bearers"? Is this yet another instance of philosophy being undermined and rendered pointless by empirical data? ] weight of precedent makes a convention socio-economically stable - e.g. forks in the west and chopsticks in the far east. Coordination conventions: Here the action requires a number of participants to coordinate, but each person's action is not clear a priori. E.g. moving a sofa, or re-dialling after a phone call gets cut, or the doorway do-ci-do.
Conventions are not mandatory - not everyone hands out cigars after a son is born. Blind coordination: both people do something w.o. waiting to see what the other is doing - e.g. driving on the left. leader-follower conventions: e.g. while moving a sofa, one becomes a leader and the other coordinates to follow. [or does the follower consider all the plans L may have, considers what L's current action fits into, and then adopts the one that may be best suited to the overall goal? RM seems to think that this would be possible only if the overall process was also "traditional". But isn't this also possible for a novel algorithm, say? ] Lewis: The conventions of language are truthfulness [say only what is true] and trust [believe what you hear]. RM feels these rules elliptically describe conventions, but may not describe "regularities" [but I think Lewis's argument is more strong. The majority of speech acts are underlied by such assumptions; and these are conventions, because we too get to follow them after being exposed to it... ] Combining conventions: RM's uses the term crisscrossing conventions - Lg is a "tangled jungle of overlapping, crisscrossing traditional patterns, reproducing themselves whole or in part for a variety of reasons. - and am I wrong to think that she is really discussing the act of combining conventions - if so, how is it different from, say the combining of constructions, or "conceptual blending", say? The notion of combining conventions seems rather similar to the idea of combining concepts... as in Langacker, say, or in Fauconnier's Conceptual Blending. [NOTE: convention as probability - high-probability events are coded more compactly and patterns for it are more easily accessed - e.g. "conventional moves in chess" - expectations are already known and bayesian rules building on these are already available. A convention in this probabilistic view, arises not by maximizing expectation alone (which would maximize benefits, and would indicate the absence of choices) but because it has already been analyzed, and the computations required to compute expectations are known. Thus the benefits are not in the search space per se, but in the meta-space of computational cost.
... a metaphysician and a philosopher of mind, language and logic at Princeton University, died on Sunday at his home in Princeton, N.J. He was 60. ... Mr. Lewis was once dubbed "a mad-dog modal realist" for his idea that any logically possible world you can think of actually exists. He believed, for instance, that there was a world with talking donkeys. ... Born in Oberlin, Ohio, on Sept. 28, 1941, Mr. Lewis was educated at Swarthmore College, Oxford University and Harvard, where he earned his doctorate, under the supervision of W. V. Quine, in 1967. He taught philosophy at U.C.L.A. from 1966 to 1970, and then at Princeton University, where he became the Class of 1943 University Professor of Philosophy. He was a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and received honorary degrees from the University of York and Cambridge University, in England. [obituary NYT: October 20, 2001]
[More complete argument: On Clear and Confused Ideas (Millikan, 2000) = OCCI] hundreds of experiments by psychologists have tried to discover how people `classify' or `categorize' items under kind (category) words such as dog, chair, and fruit. such words do not designate classes but rather units of an entirely different kind. A very few, uncompounded nouns that designate classes do exist, but words like dog, chair, and fruit are not among them.
What is a biological species? Biologist MT Ghiselin (1974, 1981) and philosopher David Hull (1978): to be members of the same species, individual animals must belong to historical lineages that have a common origin. They do not have to be similar to one another in any specified way. All dogs do not share any feature - not a gene - every dog gene has alternative forms (alleles). Similarly no properties or resemblance. Two groups of highly similar animals, if they have different historical origins, form multiple species. species are not classes that share a similarity, but rather are big, scattered, historical individuals enduring through time. [GH] However, usually the historical relationship ("blood ties") are assoc with considerable similarity in properties. Homeostasis: Each gene must help produce a viable individual frequently enough so that it can get itself reproduced sufficiently frequently so as not be eliminated from the gene pool. Diff individuals in a species resemble one another in a great variety of ways, but do not all resemble one another in any particular ways. What pulls them together as a group is not just that they have common or overlapping properties, but that they tend to have common and overlapping properties for a good reason [causality: they are caused by genetic overlap]. ... On the other hand, classes (categories) are defined by the members having certain common properties. Fuzzy classes may be defined by the members having overlapping properties, or by their having many properties in common with a paradigm, or paradigms. But the members of a class don't have to be causally like one another; they may be so by accident.
If there is a reason why one dog is likely to be similar to the next dog in a good number of respects, then there is a reason why studying one dog is likely to yield a considerable amount of probable knowledge about the next dog. ... all this knowledge is merely probable knowledge. Whatever one learns about the properties of dogs, it will not be analytic or necessary that every individual dog has each of those properties. [WN: analytic: of a proposition that is necessarily true independent of fact or experience; "`all spinsters are unmarried' is an analytic proposition") E.g. consider the class "red triangles". If one member is sweet, it doesn't say much about any other member, either necessarily or probabilistically. This is because they are not causally related. Possibility of Inductive knowledge: The value of being in a class comes from the ability to predict that one indiv will be like the next, so we can obtain knowledge without examining every member separately. [The knowledge generalizn argument may not extend the way it is proposed here. Probabilistically, if K members out of K tasted in class "red triangle" is sweet, we can construct an estimated prob 1 that all red tris are sweet. The reliability of this estimate would depend on the sample size N etc. It is of course possible that just these K were sweet, and if N>>K, then N-K/N is ~ 1, so that red-tri's are generally not sweet. This latter would also be possible for some class like dogs. Say out of 1000 dogs, 10 are blue. Then if these are the ones I see first, I may have a wrong notion of dog colour. Thus inductive knowledge about dog colour and red-tri sweetness both may be impossible. So, just as in any class, only some attrib's are similar, so also in a species. ] If empirical knowledge about a species is inductive, it would be useful to refer to it as a group, and it could acquire a name. Any group where one individual within the unit, or one part of the unit, is liable to be like another, can be called "substances," (from Aristotle). Non-philosophers may need to read this as a new technical term, but philosophers may recognize it as fairly traditional. 3. Three kinds of (Aristotelian) "substances" Aristotelian "substances" fall roughly into at least three basic sorts, which I call "historical kinds," "eternal kinds," and "individuals."
A "historical kind" (like dogs, for example) is a collection of individuals scattered over a definite spatiotemporal area. Furthermore, the individuals are causally related to one another in such a manner that each is likely to be similar to the next in a variety of aspects. [because 1. something akin to reproduction or copying has been going on; 2. members have been produced by, in, or in response to, the the same historical environment; 3. an ubiquitous causal factor often supporting the first factor- some "function" is served by members of the kind, where "function" is understood roughly in the biological sense as an effect raising the probability that its cause will be reproduced. ] Artifacts are often good examples of this - e.g. chairs. Designed for ergonomic and aesthetic preferences of humans, who are themselves much alike (for the same reasons dogs are). Moreover, the design of a chair is invariably influenced by the design of prev chairs (partly because the prev designs fit the culture) - hence chairs form a rough "historical kind." There are historical reasons, which have nothing to do with any arbitrary points of definition, why one knows roughly what to expect when someone offers to bring a chair. Musical renditions of a folk tune ... form historical kinds. The renditions are copied from other people, or from scores that had been transcribed from earlier renditions or had been copied from earlier scores. McDonald's restaurants form a historical kind. There are historical, cultural causes for their being so much alike. Professors, doctors, and businessmen form historical kinds that are especially well integrated when the groups are studied in particular historical and cultural contexts. Individual professors, doctors, and businessmen are likely to act in similar ways and to have attitudes in common as a result of: similar training handed down from person to person (reproduction or copying), and/or custom (more copying), and/or natural human dispositions (compared to dog dispositions), and/or social pressures to conform to role models (copying again), and/or legal practices handed down from univocal sources. There is a reason why it may be productive to investigate, for example, "the attitudes of American doctors toward acupuncture". These attitudes are contagious. They spread.
... are alike because of a common inner nature of some sort, such as an inner molecular structure, from which the observable properties are determined. e.g. chemical elements and compounds, or H20 which is ice, liquid water, or steam. Stars, planets, comets, asteroids, and geodes are eternal kinds, not because their properties flow always from exactly the same inner nature, but because they were formed by the same natural forces, in the same sort of circumstances, out of materials that are similar in relevant ways. [Yet one atom is quite dissimilar from another, in velocity, position, energy, mass, etc. Water, ice and steam - how are they really similar? Could this also not be historical? Why would stars not be historical, once we understand their history? w: The SUBSTANCE is that part of water that is unchanged when it turns from water to ice; it is the "bare particular", without which it would not be water. It is "bare" because it is considered without its properties and "particular" because it is not abstract. The properties that the substance has are said to inhere in the substance. Arguments for substance theory include "Arguments from Grammar" (Snow is white), and Arguments from conception. ]
The last kind of (Aristotelian) substances are individuals. Ghiselin and Hull claimed that species are actually individuals, because they are held together not by a traditional essence, but rather through historical causal connections. Like species, properties of individuals are stable. ... A species is a "homeostatic system .... amazingly well-buffered to resist change and maintain stability in the face of disturbing influences" [Eldredge and Gould (1972, p.114]. If a woman is tall, brownhaired, knowledgeable about electronics, and a good piano player today, it is likely, though not certain, that she will also possess these traits tomorrow. Individual objects are things that inductive knowledge can be collected about over time; similarly, a historical kind and, more broadly, an eternal kind are things that knowledge can be collected about over time. [I am not sure this third kind is sufficiently different from a historical kind. A living person (or an artifact) is changing from day to day, some atoms are sloughing off, some others are building up. But something continues to be similar to what it was before; this is perhaps a causal historical continuity not sufficiently diff from "historical kinds". The woman-of-yesterday and the woman-of-today are two different entities, but historically (and therefore causally) connected). ]
Thus: historical kinds, eternal kinds and individuals - three basic kinds of (Aristotelian) substances - are similar with respect to why it is possible to gain inductive knowledge about one part of such a cemented-together unity from other parts. ... there is no central set of properties, all or some of which one must be able to think of, recognize or discriminate in order to think of the (Aristotelian) substance dog, in order to learn about dogs, to understand things said about dogs, and so forth.
As an aside, this discussion reminded me of Hilary Putnam's famous twin earth scenario - if our mental categories can't be sure about identity, how can we relate to "kinds"? We begin by supposing that elsewhere in the universe there is a planet exactly like earth in virtually all respects, which we refer to as ‘Twin Earth’. (We should also suppose that the relevant surroundings of Twin Earth are identical to those of earth; it revolves around a star that appears to be exactly like our sun, and so on.) On Twin Earth there is a Twin equivalent of every person and thing here on Earth. The one difference between the two planets is that there is no water on Twin Earth. In its place there is a liquid that is superficially identical, but is chemically different, being composed not of H2O, but rather of some more complicated formula which we abbreviate as ‘XYZ’. The Twin Earthlings who refer to their language as ‘English’ call XYZ ‘water’. Finally, we set the date of our thought experiment to be several centuries ago, when the residents of Earth and Twin Earth would have no means of knowing that the liquids they called ‘water’ were H2O and XYZ respectively. The experience of people on Earth with water, and that of those on Twin Earth with XYZ would be identical. Now the question arises: when an earthling, say Oscar, and his twin on Twin Earth say 'water' do they mean the same thing? (The twin is also called 'Oscar' on his own planet, of course. Indeed, the inhabitants of that planet call their own planet 'Earth'. For convenience, we refer to this putative planet as 'Twin Earth', and extend this naming convention to the objects and people that inhabit it, in this case referring to Oscar's twin as Twin-Oscar, and twin-earth water as twater.) Ex hypothesi, their brains are molecule-for-molecule identical. Yet, at least according to Putnam, when Oscar says water, the term refers to H2O, whereas when Twin Oscar says 'water' it refers to XYZ. The result of this is that the contents of a person's brain are not sufficient to determine the reference of terms they use, as one must also examine the causal history that led to this individual acquiring the term. (Oscar, for instance, learned the word 'water' in a world filled with H2O, whereas Twin Oscar learned 'water' in a world filled with XYZ.)