Jackendoff, Ray S.;
Semantic Structures
MIT Press, 1992, 336 pages [gbook]
ISBN 026260020X, 9780262600200
topics: | language | cognitive | semantics
attempts to formulate a semantic model for argument structures. --from intro: The closing words of Chomsky's monograph Syntactic Structures are these: . . . one result of the formal study of grammatical structure is that a syntactic framework is brought to light which can support semantic analysis. Description of meaning can profitably refer to this underlying syntactic framework, although systematic semantic considerations are apparently not helpful in determining it in the first place. The notion of ''structural meaning" ... appears to be quite suspect... Nevertheless, we do find many important correlations, quite naturally, between syntactic structure and meaning; or, to put it differently, we find that the grammatical devices are used quite systematically. These correlations could form part of the subject matter for a more general theory of language concerned with syntax and semantics and their points of connection. (Chomsky 1957, 108) To develop the "more general theory" that Chomsky envisions, one must confront two basic problems: * Problem of Meaning : characterize the phenomena that a theory of meaning is to account for, and to develop a formal treatment of semantic intuitions. In particular, a formal theory of meaning must be expressive enough to account for the distinctions of meaning made by language users, and for the semantic relations — including inference — that speakers can draw among words, phrases, and sentences. It must also provide the basis on which speakers relate words, phrases, and sentences to their understanding of the nonlinguistic world, so that they can make judgments of reference and truth. * Problem of Correspondence is to characterize the relationship between the formal treatment of meaning and the formal structure of syntax. [In 2000+, Cog Linguists might ask: but is meaning expressible formally? the key q. may be how to express meaning. surely, structures as in formal algebra seem inadequate? ] These two problems are clearly not entirely separate. One's choice of semantic formalism has an immediate effect on possible solutions to the Problem of Correspondence. Other things being equal, we should rate more highly a solution to the Problem of Meaning that permits a more perspicuous solution to the Problem of Correspondence. On the other hand, one cannot work out a theory of meaning solely for the purpose of simplifying the Problem of Correspondence: there are many other boundary conditions that must simultaneously be satisfied. The present study is an exploration of the interaction between these two problems.
There is a fundamental tension in the ordinary language term concept. On the one hand, concepts seem to be "out there in the world" - e.g. "the Newtonian concept of mass". One "grasps concepts" just as one grasps a physical object, except that one does it with one's mind. On th other hand, a concept within one's head is a private entity, a product of the imagination that can be conveyed to others only by means of language, gesture, drawing, or some other imperfect means. Chomsky: e-language = language seen as an external artifact, i-language = lg as a body of internally encoded information For characterizing the mental resources that make possible human knowledge and experience of the world, it is crucial to choose I-concepts rather than E-concepts [so as to remain com[patible with generative linguistics.] p.8
How can a child acquire the rules of syntax on the basis of the fragmentary evidence available? In particular, how does the child induce rules from instances of well-formed sentences? This question is rendered especially pointed by the fact that the community of generative linguists, with all their collective intelligence, have not been able to fully determine the syntactic rules of English in over thirty years of research, supported by centuries of traditional grammatical description; yet of course every normal child exposed to English masters the grammar by the age of ten or so. This apparent paradox of language acquisition motivates the central hypothesis of generative linguistics: that children come to the task of language learning equipped with an innate Universal Grammar that narrowly restricts the options available for the grammar they are trying to acquire. The driving issue in generative linguistics, then, is to determine the form of Universal Grammar, consonant both with the variety of human languages and also with their learnability. p.10