Gazzaniga, Michael S.;
The Cognitive Neurosciences IV (fourth ed.)
MIT Press, 2009, 1294 pages
ISBN 026201341X, 9780262013413
topics: | cognitive |
Michael Gazzaniga, a leader and prime mover in neuroscience, has been editing a volume titled Cognitive Neurosciences, with the different editions numbered III, IV, etc, and sometimes "New Cognitive Neurosciences". Some articles are added and dropped between versions, others are edited or re-titled or authorships changed. This compilation, from 2009, is the most updated, and also the most voluminous. Many fascinating overview articles. A great text to introduce concepts in cognitive Science.
Philosopher Ned Block compares the three frameworks for theories of consciousness that "are taken most seriously by neuroscientists": * Consciousness is a BIOLOGICAL state of the brain [The idea] that consciousness is some sort of biological state derives from Democritus (Kirk, Raven, & Schofield, 1983) and Hobbes (1989), but was put in modern form in the 1950s by Place (1956), Smart (1959), and Feigl (1958). (See also Block, 1978; Crane, 2000; Lamme, 2003.) Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? Br. J. Psychol., 47, 44–50. Crane, T. (2000). The origins of qualia. In T. Crane & S. Patterson (Eds.), History of the mind-body problem (pp. 169–194). New York: Routledge. Lamme, V. (2003). Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends Cogn. Sci., 7, 12–18. * Global workspace perspective The global workspace account of consciousness was first suggested by Bernard Baars (1988) and has been developed in a more neural direction by Stanislas Dehaene, Jean-Pierre Changeux, and their colleagues (Dehaene, Changeux, Nacchache, Sackur, & Sergent, 2006). The account presupposes a neural network approach in which there is competition among neural coalitions involving both frontal and sensory areas (Koch, 2004), the winning coalitions being conscious. * Higher order thought (HOT) [explains consuciousness in terms of of higher order states]. experience is phenomenally conscious only in virtue of another state that is about the experience (Armstrong, 1978; Lycan, 1996a; Byrne, 1997; Carruthers, 2000; Byrne, 2001b; Rosenthal, 2005a). This perspective comes in many varieties, depending on, among other things, whether the monitoring state is a thought or a perception. The version to be discussed here says that the higher order state is a thought (“higher order thought” is abbreviated as HOT) and that a conscious experience of red consists in a representation of red in the visual system accompanied by a thought in the same subject to the effect that the subject is having the experience of red. --- The comparison of these three theories features the “explanatory gap” (Nagel, 1974; Levine, 1983), the fact that we have no idea why the neural basis of an experience is the neural basis of that experience rather than another experience or no experience at all. It is argued that the biological framework handles the explanatory gap better than do the global workspace or higher order views. The article does not discuss quantum theories or “panpsychist” accounts according to which consciousness is a feature of the smallest particles of inorganic matter (Chalmers, 1996; Rosenberg, 2004). Nor does it discuss the “representationist” proposals (Tye, 2000; Byrne, 2001a) that are popular among philosophers but not neuroscientists.
Phenomenal consciousness is “what it is like” to have an experience (Nagel, 1974). Any discussion of the physical basis of phenomenal consciousness (henceforth just consciousness) has to acknowledge the “explanatory gap” (Nagel, 1974; Levine, 1983): nothing that we now know, indeed nothing that we have been able to hypothesize or even fantasize, gives us an understanding of why the neural basis of the experience of green that I now have when I look at my screen saver is the neural basis of that experience as opposed to another experience or no experience at all.
Nagel puts the point in terms of the distinction between subjectivity and objectivity: the experience of green is a subjective state, but brain states are objective, and we do not understand how a subjective state could be an objective state or even how a subjective state could be based in an objective state. The problem of closing the explanatory gap (the “Hard Problem” as Chalmers, 1996, calls it) has four important aspects:
(1) we do not see a hint of a solution; (2) we have no good argument that there is no solution that another kind of being could grasp or that we may be able to grasp at a later date (but see McGinn, 1991); so (3) the explanatory gap is not intrinsic to consciousness; and (4) most importantly for current purposes, recognizing the first three points requires no special theory of consciousness. All scientifically oriented accounts should agree that consciousness is in some sense based in the brain; once this fact is accepted, the problem arises of why the brain basis of this experience is the basis of this one rather than another one or none, and it becomes obvious that nothing now known gives a hint of an explanation. The explanatory gap was first brought to the attention of scientists through the work of Nagel (1974) and Crick and Koch (Crick, 1994; Crick & Koch, 1998). Many would argue that the candid recognition of what we do not understand played an important role in fueling the incredible wave of research that still engulfs us. There is a fine line between acknowledging the explanatory gap and surrendering to dualism.The explanatory gap and dualism
Dualism is the view that there is some aspect of the mind that is not physical (Chalmers, 1996). It comes in many varieties, but the issues to be discussed do not depend on any specific variety. Let us start with a historical analogy (Nagel, 1974). A pre-Socratic philosopher would have no way of understanding how heat could be a kind of motion or of how light could be a kind of vibration. Why? Because the pre-Socratic philosopher did not have the appropriate concepts of motion — namely, the concept of kinetic energy and its role — or of vibration — namely, the concepts involved in the wave theory of light — that would allow an understanding of how such different concepts could pick out the same phenomenon. What is a concept? A concept is a mental representation usable in thought. We often have more than one concept of the same thing. The concept light and the concept electromagnetic radiation of 400–700 nm pick out the same phenomenon. What the pre-Socratic philosopher lacks is a concept of light and an appropriate concept of vibration (one that requires a whole theory). What is missing for the pre-Socratic is not just the absence of a theoretical definition but a lack of understanding of what things are grouped together from a scientific point of view. We now realize that ripples in a pond, sound, and light are all phenomena of the same kind: waves. And we now realize that burning, rusting, and metabolizing are all cases of oxidation (Churchland, 2002), but the pre-Socratics, given their framework in which the basic categories were fire, earth, air, and water, would have had no way to grasp these facts. One upshot is that if superscientists of the future were to tell us what consciousness is, we probably would not have the conceptual machinery to understand, just as the pre-Socratic would not have the conceptual machinery to understand that heat is a kind of motion or that light is a kind of vibration. Armed with this idea, we can see how to steer between the explanatory gap and dualism. What we lack is an objective neuroscientific concept that would allow us to see how it could pick out the same phenomenon as our subjective concept of the experience of green. And we can expect that we do not even have the right subjective concept of the experience of green, since we are not sure what subjective phenomena truly should be grouped together. The resolution of the apparent conflict between the explanatory gap and physicalism is that subjectivity and objectivity can be seen as properties of concepts rather than properties of the states that the concepts are concepts of. This idea, that we can see arguments that apparently indicate ontological dualism — that is, a dualism of objects or substances or properties — as really an argument for conceptual dualism, stems from Nagel (1974) and Loar (1990/1997) and is sometimes called New Wave physicalism (see Horgan & Tienson, 2001). Another way of seeing the point is to consider Jackson's (1982) famous thought experiment concerning Mary, a neuroscientist of the distant future who knows everything there is to know about the scientific basis of color experience, but has grown up in a black-and-white environment. When she sees red for the first time, she learns what it is like to see red, despite already knowing all the scientific facts about seeing red. Does this show that the fact of what it is like to see red is not a scientific fact? No, because we can think of what Mary learns in terms of her acquiring a subjective concept of a state that she already had an objective concept of. Imagine someone who already knows that Lake Michigan is filled with H2O, but learns something new: that Lake Michigan is filled with water. What this person learns is not a new fact but a new piece of knowledge, involving a new concept, of a fact the person already knew. Similarly, Mary acquires new knowledge, but that new knowledge does not go beyond the scientific facts that she already knew about, and so does not support any kind of dualism. (This line of thought is debated in Block, 2006; White, 2006.) Importantly, this line of reasoning does not do away with the explanatory gap but rather reconceives it as a failure to understand how a subjective and an objective concept can pick out the same thing. These points about different concepts of the same thing have sometimes been used to try to dissolve the explanatory gap (Papineau, 2002). The idea is that the false appearance of an explanatory gap arises from the gap between a subjective concept of a phenomenally conscious state and an objective concept of the same state. But note: I can think the thought that the color I am now experiencing as I look at an orange (invoking a subjective concept of orange) is identical to the color between red and yellow (invoking an objective concept of orange). But this use of the two kinds of concepts engenders no explanatory gap. [goes on to relate the explanatory gap to the three theories being considered.]
Contents
PrefaceI. DEVELOPMENT AND EVOLUTION
Introduction Pasko Rakic and Leo M. Chalupa 1. Development of the Primate Cerebral Cortex Pasko Rakic, Jon I. Arellano, and Joshua Breunig 2. Early Development of Neuronal Circuitry of the Human Prefrontal Cortex Ivica Kostovic and Milos Judas 3. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Human Uniqueness Todd M. Preuss 4. Unraveling the Role of Neuronal Activity in the Formation of Eye-Specific Connections Leo M. Chalupa and Andrew D. Huberman 5. Brain Changes Underlying the Development of Cognitive Control and Reasoning Silvia A. Bunge, Allyson P. Mackey, and Kirstie J. WhitakerII. PLASTICITY
Introduction Helen Neville and Mriganka Sur 6. Patterning and Plasticity of Maps in the Mammalian Visual Pathway Sam Horng and Mriganka Sur 7. Synaptic Plasticity and Spatial Representations in the Hippocampus Jonathan R. Whitlock and Edvard I. Moser 8. Visual Cortical Plasticity and Perceptual Learning Wu Li and Charles D. Gilbert 9. Characterizing and Modulating Neuroplasticity of the Adult Human Brain Alvaro Pascual-Leone 10. Exercising Your Brain: Training-Related Brain Plasticity Daphne Bavelier, C. Shawn Green, and Matthew W. G. Dye 11. Profiles of Development and Plasticity in Human Neurocognition Courtney Stevens and Helen NevilleIII. ATTENTION
Introduction Steven J. Luck and George R. Mangun 12. Attention: Theoretical and Psychological Perspectives Anne Treisman 13. Mechanisms of Selective Attention in the Human Visual System: Evidence from Neuroimaging Sabine Kastner, Stephanie A. McMains, and Diane M. Beck 14. The Frontoparietal Attention Network Maurizio Corbetta, Chad M. Sylvester, and Gordon L. Shulman 15. Spatiotemporal Analysis of Visual Attention Jens-Max Hopf, Hans-Jochen Heinze, Mircea A. Schoenfeld, and Steven A. Hillyard 16. Integration of Conflict Detection and Attentional Control Mechanisms: Combined ERP and fMRI Studies George R. Mangun, Clifford D. Saron, and Bong J. Walsh 17. A Right Perisylvian Neural Network for Human Spatial Orienting Hans-Otto Karnath 18. Spatial Deficits and Selective Attention Lynn C. Robertson 19. The Effect of Attention on the Responses of Individual Visual Neurons John H. R. Maunsell 20. Selective Attention Through Selective Neuronal Synchronization Thilo Womelsdorf and Pascal FriesIV. SENSATION AND PERCEPTION
Introduction J. Anthony Movshon and Brian A. Wandell 21. Grandmother Cells, Symmetry, and Invariance: How the Term Arose and What the Facts Suggest Horace Barlow 22. Olfaction: From Percept to Molecule Yaara Yeshurun, Hadas Lapid, Rafi Haddad, Shani Gelstien, Anat Arzi, Lee Sela, Aharon Weisbrod, Rehan Khan, and Noam Sobel 23. Auditory Masking with Complex Stimuli Virginia M. Richards and Gerald Kidd, Jr. 24. Insights into Human Auditory Processing Gained from Perceptual Learning Beverly A. Wright and Yuxuan Zhang 25. Auditory Object Analysis Timothy D. Griffiths, Sukhbinder Kumar, Katharina von Kriegstein, Tobias Overath, Klaas E. Stephan, and Karl J. Friston 26. The Cone Photoreceptor Mosaic in Normal and Defective Color Vision Joseph Carroll, Geunyoung Yoon, and David R. Williams 27. Bayesian Approaches to Color Vision David H. Brainard 28. Wiring of Receptive Fields and Functional Maps in Primary Visual Cortex Dario L. Ringach 29. Encoding and Decoding with Neural Populations in the Primate Cortex Eyal Seidemann, Yuzhi Chen, and Wilson S. Geisler 30. Perceptual Filling-in: From Experimental Data to Neural Network Modeling Rainer Goebel and Peter De Weerd 31. Neural Transformation of Object Information by Ventral Pathway Visual Cortex Charles E. Connor, Anitha Pasupathy, Scott Brincat, and Yukako Yamane 32. The Cognitive and Neural Development of Face Recognition in Humans Elinor McKone, Kate Crookes, and Nancy Kanwisher 33. Roles of Visual Area MT in Depth Perception Gregory C. DeAngelis 34. Multisensory Integration for Heading Perception in Macaque Visual Cortex Dora E. Angelaki, Yong Gu, and Gregory C. DeAngelis 35. Visual Stability during Saccadic Eye Movements Concetta Morrone and David Burr 36. Optimal Estimation in Sensory Systems Eero P. SimoncelliV. MOTOR SYSTEMS
Introduction Scott T. Grafton and Emilio Bizzi 37. Neurobiology of Coordinate Transformations Emilio Bizzi and Ferdinando A. Mussa-Ivaldi 38. Basal Ganglia and Cerebellar Circuits with the Cerebral Cortex Richard P. Dum and Peter L. Strick 39. The Basal Ganglia and Cognition Ann M. Graybiel and Jonathan W. Mink 40. Computational Neuroanatomy of Voluntary Motor Control Reza Shadmehr and John W. Krakauer 41. Forward Models and State Estimation in Posterior Parietal Cortex Grant H. Mulliken and Richard A. Andersen 42. Parallels between Sensory and Motor Information Processing Emanuel Todorov 43. The Mirror Neuron System: A Motor-Based Mechanism for Action and Intention Understanding Giacomo Rizzolatti, Leonardo Fogassi, and Vittorio Gallese 44. Relative Hierarchies and the Representation of Action Scott T. Grafton, L. Aziz-Zadeh, and R. B. IvryVI. MEMORY
Introduction Daniel L. Schacter 45. Comparative Analysis of the Cortical Afferents, Intrinsic Projections, and Interconnections of the Parahippocampal Region in Monkeys and Rats Wendy A. Suzuki 46. Medial Temporal Lobe Function and Human Memory Yael Shrager and Larry R. Squire 47. Reconsolidation: A Possible Bridge between Cognitive and Neuroscientific Views of Memory Karim Nader 48. The Dynamic Interplay between Cognitive Control and Memory Elizabeth A. Race, Brice A. Kuhl, David Badre, and Anthony D. Wagner 49. Phases of Influence: How Emotion Modulates the Formation and Retrieval of Declarative Memories Elizabeth A. Kensinger 50. Individual Differences in the Engagement of the Cortex during an Episodic Memory Task Michael B. Miller 51. Constructive Memory and the Simulation of Future Events Daniel L. Schacter, Donna Rose Addis, and Randy L. BucknerVII. LANGUAGE
Introduction Alfonso Caramazza 52. The Cortical Organization of Phonological Processing Gregory Hickok 53. Morphological Processes in Language Production Kevin A. Shapiro and Alfonso Caramazza 54. Ventral and Dorsal Contributions to Word Reading Laurent Cohen and Stanislas Dehaene 55. The Neural Basis of Syntactic Processing David Caplan 56. Semantic Unification Peter Hagoort, Giosuè Baggio, and Roel M. Willems 57. Early Language Acquisition: Neural Substrates and Theoretical Models Patricia K. Kuhl 58. Genetics of Language Franck Ramus and Simon E. Fisher 59. The Biology and Evolution of Language: “Deep Homology” and the Evolution of Innovation W. Tecumseh FitchVIII. THE EMOTIONAL AND SOCIAL BRAIN
Introduction Todd F. Heatherton and Joseph E. LeDoux 60. Ontogeny of Infant Fear Learning and the Amygdala Regina M. Sullivan, Stephanie Moriceau, Charlis Raineki, and Tania L. Roth 61. Emotional Reaction and Action: From Threat Processing to Goal-Directed Behavior Joseph E. LeDoux, Daniela Schiller, and Christopher Cain 62. Interactions of Emotion and Attention in Perception Patrik Vuilleumier and Tobias Brosch 63. Context Effects and the Amygdala Paul J. Whalen and F. Caroline Davis 64. Neurogenetic Studies of Variability in Human Emotion Ahmad R. Hariri 65. Components of a Social Brain Jason P. Mitchell and Todd F. Heatherton 66. The Neural Basis of Emotion Regulation: Making Emotion Work for You and Not Against You Jennifer S. Beer 67. Sharing the Emotions of Others: The Neural Bases of Empathy Tania Singer and Susanne Leiberg 68. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Judgment Joshua D. GreeneIX. HIGHER COGNITIVE FUNCTIONS
Introduction Elizabeth A. Phelps 69. Prefrontal Substrate of Human Relational Reasoning Barbara J. Knowlton and Keith J. Holyoak 70. Decision Making and Prefrontal Executive Function Christopher Summerfield and Etienne Koechlin 71. Circuits in Mind: The Neural Foundations for Object Concepts Alex Martin 72. Semantic Cognition: Its Nature, Its Development, and Its Neural Basis James L. McClelland, Timothy T. Rogers, Karalyn Patterson, Katia Dilkina, and Matthew Lambon Ralph 73. Two Views of Brain Function Marcus E. Raichle 74. The Neuroeconomics of Simple Goal-Directed Choice (Circa 2008) Antonio Rangel 75. Neuroeconomics and the Study of Valuation Paul W. Glimcher 76. Emotion and Decision Making Elizabeth A. Phelps and Mauricio R. DelgadoX. CONSCIOUSNESS
Introduction Christof Koch 77. Comparing the Major Theories of Consciousness Ned Block 78. Recovery of Consciousness after Brain Injury: An Integrative Research Paradigm for the Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness Nicholas D. Schiff 79. The Neurobiology of Consciousness Christof Koch 80. Visual Awareness Geraint Rees 81. The Role of Feedback in Visual Attention and Awareness Stephen L. Macknik and Susana Martinez-Conde 82. Emotion and Consciousness Michael Koenigs and Ralph Adolphs 83. Volition and the Function of Consciousness Hakwan Lau 84. Toward a Theory of Consciousness Giulio Tononi and David BalduzziXI. PERSPECTIVES
85. Mapping Cognitive Neuroscience: Two-Dimensional Perspectives on Twenty Years of Cognitive Neuroscience Research John T. Bruer 86. Reflections on the Cognitive Neuroscience of Language Sheila E. Blumstein 87. Why the Imagery Debate Won't Go Away Stephen M. Kosslyn, William L. Thompson, and Giorgio Ganis 88. Looking Toward the Future: Perspectives on Examining the Architecture and Function of the Human Brain as a Complex System Michael S. Gazzaniga, Karl W. Doron, and Chadd M. Funk 89. The Landscape of Cognitive Neuroscience: Challenges, Rewards, and New Perspectives Elissa M. Aminoff, Daniela Balslev, Paola Borroni, Ronald E. Bryan, Elizabeth F. Chua, Jasmin Cloutier, Emily S. Cross, Trafton Drew, Chadd M. Funk, Ricardo Gil-da-Costa, Scott A. Guerin, Julie L. Hall, Kerry E. Jordan, Ayelet N. Landau, Istvan Molnar-Szakacs, Leila Montaser-Kouhsari, Jonas K. Olofsson, Susanne Quadflieg, Leah H. Somerville, Jocelyn L. Sy, Lucina Q. Uddin, and Makiko Yamada
to contribute some excerpts from your favourite book to book excerptise. send us a plain text file with page-numbered extracts from your favourite book. You can preface your extracts with a short review.
email to (bookexcerptise [at] gmail [dot] com).We reply to all feedback!
bookexcerptise is maintained by a small group of editors. get in touch with us! bookexcerptise [at] gmail [dot] .com. This article last updated on : 2014 Aug 21