book excerptise:   a book unexamined is wasting trees

Consciousness Explained

Daniel Clement Dennett and Paul Weiner (ill.)

Dennett, Daniel Clement; Paul Weiner (ill.);

Consciousness Explained

Little, Brown and Co., 1991, 528 pages

ISBN 0316180661, 9780316180665

topics: |  philoosphy | cognitive | brain | mind-body | ai | consciousness

1. The brain in the vat

Suppose evil scientists removed your brain from your body while
you slept, and set it up in a life-support system in a vat. Suppose they
then set out to trick you into believing that you were not just a brain
in a vat, but still up and about, engaging in a normally embodied round
of activities in the real world. This old saw, the brain in the vat, is a
favorite thought experiment in the toolkit of many philosophers. It is
a modern-day version of Descartes's (1641)1 evil demon, an imagined
illusionist bent on tricking Descartes about absolutely everything, including
his own existence. But as Descartes observed, even an infinitely
powerful evil demon couldn't trick him into thinking he himself existed
if he didn't exist: cogito ergo sum, "I think, therefore I am."

philosophers have assumed for the sake of argument that however technically
difficult the task might be, it is "possible in principle." One should be
leery of these possibilities in principle. It is also possible in principle
to build a stainless-steel ladder to the moon, and to write out, in
alphabetical order, all intelligible English conversations consisting of
less than a thousand words. But neither of these are remotely possible in
fact and sometimes an impossibility in fact is theoretically more
interesting than a possibility in principle,

We are — and should be — skeptical of reports of very strong
hallucinations... (It was primarily the telltale strength of the
hallucinations reported by Carlos Castaneda in The Teachings of Don Juan: A
Yaqui Way of Knowledge [19681 that first suggested to scientists that the
book, in spite of having been a successful Ph.D. thesis in anthropology at
UCLA, was fiction, not fact.)

The problem with consciousness:


Theme running through the book: Consciousness is treated by us much like
magic is.  

    a card magician has many standard ways of giving the victim the illusion
    that he is exercising his free choice in what cards on the table he
    examines, when in fact there is only one card that may be turned
    over. p.10

[consciousness is like hallucinations that may be be produced in a brain], a
way that harnesses the very freewheeling curiosity of the victim. 10

from On Baars, “The double life of B.F. Skinner. . . “, by Daniel Dennett, 2002

Is consciousness real? Of course it is – as long as you don’t understand it as
magic, but for some people, consciousness is magic or it is nothing at all.
Are there really such people? Yes, many. Speaking for them, for instance, is
Robert Wright:

[from Robert Wright, 2000, Nonzero: the Logic of Human Destiny, Pantheon, p.425]

   "I'm writing a book on magic." I explain, and I'm asked, "Real magic?" By
   real magic people mean miracles, thaumaturgical acts, and supernatural
   powers. "No." I answer: "Conjuring tricks, not real magic." ~ Lee Siegel,
   in his fascinating history of Indian street magic,  Net of Magic: Wonders
   and Deceptions in India, (Univ. of  Chicago Press, 1991)  

    Real magic in other words, refers to the magic that is not real, while the
     magic that is real, that can actually be done, is /not real magic/. "

In our brains there is a cobbled-together collection of specialist
brain circuits, which, thanks to a faniily of habits inculcated partly by
culture and partly by individual self-exploration, conspire together to
produce a more or less orderly, more r less effective, more or less welldesigned
virtual machine, the Joyce:in machine. By yoking these independently
evolved specialist organs together in common cause, and
thereby giving their union vastly erhanced powers, this virtual machine,
this software of the brain, performs a sort of internal political
miracle: It creates a virtual captain of the crew, without elevating any
one of them to long-term dictatorial power. Who's in charge? First one
coalition and then another... p. 228

It looks magical, but as every stage magician knows, the appearance of magic
is heightened by the fact that an audience can generally be counted on to
exaggerate the phenomenon in need of explanation.

Stage magicians know that a collection of cheap tricks will often suffice to
produce "magic," and so does Mother the ultimate gadgeteer.

[Thus the brain too, is a set of cobbled together cheap tricks. 
the fact that we find them difficult to see is because of an illusion we have
created for ourselves, the illusion of consciousness itself, which fills in
the huge gaps and creates this magical, coherent whole.  This seems to be the
thrust of Dennett's arguments. 

But perhaps the tricks aren't that cheap, after all! ] 

3. A party game: "psychoanalysis"


In this game one person, the dupe, is told that while he is out of the room,
one member of the assembled party will be called upon to relate a recent
dream. This will give everybody else in the room the story line of that dream
so that when the dupe returns to the room and begins questioning the assembled
party, the dreamer's identity will be hidden in the crowd of responders. The
dupe's job is to ask yes/no questions of the assembled group until he has
figured out the dream narrative to a suitable degree of detail, at which point
the dupe is to psychoanalyze the dreamer, and use the analysis to identify him
or her.

Once the dupe is out of the room, the host explains to the rest of the party
that no one is to relate a dream, that the party is to answer the dupe's
questions according to the following simple rule: if the last letter of the
last word of the question is in the first half of the alphabet.  the questions
is to be answered in the affirmative, and all other questions are to be
answered in the negative, with one proviso: a noncontradiction override rule
to the effect that later questions are not to be given answers that contradict
earlier answers. For example:

	Q: Is the dream about a girl?
	A: Yes.

but if later our forgetful dupe asks

	Q: Are there any female characters in it?
	A: Yes [in spite of the final t, applying the noncontradiction override]

When the dupe eventually relates the dream to a dreamer, the assembled party
gleefully retorts that the dupe himself is the author of the "dream." ... but
in one sense, the dream simply has no author, and that is the whole
point. Here we see a process of narrative production, of detail accumulation,
with no authorial intentions or plans at all — an illusion with no
illusionist.

[Argues that perception is similar in that it incorporates] a few
"expectation-driven" rounds of hypothesis testing.  Theories of perception in
the 1980s (e.g., Neisser, 1967): 

     after a certain amount of "preprocessing" has occurred in the early or
     peripheral layers of the perceptual system, objects are identified,
     recognized, categorized — by generate-and-test cycles.


---

What distinguishes any old piece of matter from those
that we call "animate"?  Why are some physical
patterns in the universe privileged of feeling sensations and having
experiences?  Presents a strongly non-dualist view of consciousness.  Much of
the first third of the book is an attack on cartesian duality.  The middle
part deals with work (from 80s) in neuropsychology and AI and at artificial models that

Chapter 3: How are animals different from robots?
E.g. Descartes believed that animals were just elaborate machines.  Human
bodies, and even human brains, were machines.  It was only our nonmechanical,
nonphysical minds that make human beings [and only humans] intelligent and
conscious. p.43, footnote

Phenomenology: An umbrella term to cover all the items of conscious
experience: thoughts, smells, itches, imagined purple cows.
History of the term:
Kant: distinguishes "phenomena" - things as they appear, from "noumena",
things as they are.  In the 19th c. Phenomenology = descriptive study of any
subject matter, in a neutral or pre-theoretical manner.  The philosophical
school of Phenomenology dev 20th c around work by Edmund Husserl, aimed at
finding new foundation for all knowledge / philosophy.  p.44-5

Ch 6: Time and Experience 139


covers the fascinating work of Benjamin Libet:

stimulations given to left hand, and to corresp part of the right
somatosensory cortex.  Both stimulations take about 500ms to reach "neuronal
adequacy" - a conscious experience of a tingle.  However, when stimulations
are given to the hand, these are "automatically "referred backwards in
time".

More strikingly, Libet reported instances in which a patient's left cortex
(right hand area) was stimulated before his left hand was ==> this should
give rise to two tingles - first right hand (cortically induced) and then
left hand.  However, patients reported the opposite, "first left, then
right". p.154-5]

Libet's direct brain stimulation experiment: Dualism 153


It has long been known that stimulation of locations on the somatosensory
cortex (a strip conveniently located across the top of the brain) produces
the experience in the patient of sensations on corresponding parts of the
body. For instance, stimulation of a point on the left somatosensory cortex
can produce the sensation of a brief tingle in the subject's right hand. 154

Libet compared the time course of such cortically induced tingles to
similar sensations produced in the more usual way, by applying a brief
electrical pulse to the hand itself (Libet, 1965, 1981, 1982, 1985b; Libet et
al., 1979; see also Popper and Ecclos, 1977; Dennett, 1979b; Churchland,
1981a, 1981b; Honderich, 1984:1.

Libet asked his patients which came first, the hand-tingle that started in
the cortex or the hand-tingle sent from the hand. From the data he gathered,
he argued that while in each case it took considerable time (approximately
500 msec) from onset of stimulation to "neuronal adequacy" (the point at
which he claims that cortical processes culminate to yield a conscious
experience of a tingle), when the hand itself was stimulated, the experience
was "automatically" "referred backwards in time," and was felt to happen
before the tingle produced by brain stimulation itself.

Most strikingly, Libet reported instances in which a patient's left cortex
was stimulated before his left hand was stimulated, which one would tend to
think would surely give rise to two felt tingles: first right hand
(cortically induced) and then left hand. In fact, however, the subjective
report was reversed: "first left, then right."

Libet has interpreted his results as raising a serious challenge to
materialism:". . . a dissociation between the timings of the corresponding
and events would seem to raise serious though not insurmountable difficulties
for the.. . theory of psychoneural identity" (Libet et al., 1979,
p. 222). According to Sir John Eccies, a Nobel laureate in medicine for his
research in neurophysiology, this challenge cannot be met: p.155

	This antedating procedure does not seem to be explicable by any
	neurophysiological process. Presumably it is a strategy that has been
	learnt by the self-conscious mind. . . the antedating sensory
	experience is attributable to the ability of the self-conscious mind
	to make slight temporal adjustments, i.e., to play tricks with time.
	[Popper and Eccles, 1977, p. 3641

More recently, the mathematician and physicist Roger Penrose
(1989) has suggested that a materialistic explanation of Libet's phenomena
would require a revolution in fundamental physics.

[lengthy discussion of proposals for how the paradox arises - the signal is
back-referred to the hand, and then travels back etc....]

Libet's Subjective Delay experiment : post-facto consciousness? 162


He asked normal subjects (not neurosurgery patients) to make "spontaneous"
decisions to flex one hand at the wrist while noting the position of a spot
on a revolving disk (the "second hand" on a clock, in effect) at the precise
time they formed the intention (Libet, 1985a, 1987, 1989). Afterwards (a few
seconds later), subjects reported where the spot was at the moment they
decided to flex their wrist.

... found evidence that these "conscious decisions" lagged between
350 and 400msec behind the onset of "readiness potentials" he
was able to record from scalp electrodes,

concludes that "cerebral initiation of a spontaneous voluntary act begins
unconsciously" (1 985a, p. 529).

conscious intentions to act [at least in the Libet-an tasks] are put into
registration with the brain events that actually initiate the acts, there is
an offset in the 300-500msec range.


Other review

Owen Flannagan, Consciousness Reconsidered, chapter 3, section 3:
[In reference to Daniel Dennett's Consciousness Explained, 1991), :

The theory of "neural Darwinism" or "neuronal group selection" helps
bring together and extend some of the insights about brain
composition, structure, function, and evolution discussed so far
(Edelman 1987, 1989; also see Changeux 1985). Five ideas are
especially important.

First, it is mathematically inconceivable that the human genome
specifies the entire wiring diagram of the brain. The genome,
powerful as it is, contains too few instructions by several orders
of magnitiude to build a fully funcitonal brain. The synaptic
connections that evolve in the brain over time are the complex
causal outcome of genotypic instructions, endogenous biochemical
processes, plus vast amounts of individually unique interactions
between organism and environment (Edelman 1989, 30 Hundert 1989,
237). It follows that talk of the brain as hard-wired is
misleading. To be sure, the overall structure of the brain is fixed
by our genes and certain neuronal paths, and certain specific areas
are designed to serve certain dedicated functions. But the "wires"
in the brain are soft, even those built during fetal development
and those serving specific functions. Furthermore, all the wires
are capable of being drawn into novel and complex connections with
indefinitely many other segments of the neural network. The key to
our magnificent abilities as anticipation machines involves fixing
gross architecture while leaving the development of connections at
the microstructural level undedicated and adaptable.

Second and relatedly, individual brains are extraordinarily diverse
in terms of structure ond connectivity. Identity theory has some
credibility in the domain of sensory experience. Certain
characteristic neural patterns subserve similar cross-personal
sensory experiences. But by and large most mental states probably
do no involve strict identites between types of mental and neural
states. Thus one and the same conscious mental state, for example,
believing that a speeding fire engine is coming from behind, is
almost certainly subserved by compositionally distinct neural
states in all the different drivers who have that thought. Once
massive connectivity is added in, it is no surprise that this
thought kicks off a series of other, different thoughts for each of
us. Once person worries about the victims and their property, and
another that he will be delayed. A third is thrown into a Proustian
reminiscence of summer nights in his childhood spent with
grandfather, the fire chief, at the station. He feels the humid
summer breeze on his face as he rides to a fire, and the smells of
burning embers and pictures of lonely stone chimneys well up in
him. Neural connectivity is the mother of "meaning holism" and the
"drift of thought" the way the meaning of each term connects
idiosyncratically with the meaning of many others. We are good at
keeping attention focused, but certain events send thought reeling
to unanticipated places, some welcome, others not. Neural
connectivity helps explain why this happens so easily.

The third, fourth, and fifth theses of neural Darwinism further
clarify the prospect for a complex form of mind-brain identity
theory and indicate some of the problems such a theory will
face. The third thesis is that neuronal ensembles projecting
through many levels are selected during experiences to map and
thereby to represent certain saliencies. Which ensembles represent
what is jointly determined by the genetically specified
receptivities of different neural locaitons (so visual processing
takes place in areas dedicated to vision and not to audition) and
by the neuronal groups available for selection and strengthening at
the time a stimulus is presented. But the jobs of all ensembles are
not assigned in advance, as they are, for example, on the view that
the mind contains all concepts innately. On such a view, experience
merely acts to trigger what is there (Fodor 1975, 1981). On the
neural-selctionist view, the brain is a vast territory with
contours roughed out by nature and more than enough room for all
comers. Experiences come looking for squatter's rights, for room to
make a life. The brain makes room in various ways. Sometimes it
simply gives over unclaimed terrain; other times it sets up
time-sharing and multiple-tenancy arrangements. Selection is
involved in that the world plays an important part in determining
which neuronal groups are activated for what roles. It does not
simply trigger neuronal groups preset to work for a particular
boss, should he turn up, and give the marching orders they
passively await. Nonetheless, once a neuronal group is assigned to
a task, that group shows up regularly for the job.

Fourth and relatedly, the neuronal network retains representations,
but not in permanently coded files. It retains representations as
dispositions to reactivate distributed activation patterns selected
during previous experience. Once a particular distributed
activation pattern has reached an equilibrial state so that it is
activated by a certain type of stimulus pattern, it frames novel
occurent stimulation with that activation pattern. This leads to
quick and easy identification of the stimulation and, depending on
its connections to other neuronal groups, to the right motor
repsponse. The neuronal groups are selected to detect certain
constellations of features. The groups are extremely sensitive but
not overly fussy. This explains why we are so quick to identify
degraded stimuli, for example, letters written in new and obscure
handwriting. The right pattern of activation is turned on by any
stimulus that possesses a sufficient number, or some adquately
patterned configuration, of the relevant features. The stimuli need
not be exactly the same as the stimuli that the neuronal group was
initially trained to detect. Indeed, a system that could only
recognize duplicates of previous stimuli would be of no use at all
in our fluid ecological surround. Recognition and recall do not
involve permanent storage, and thus lost space each time a
particular pattern becomes recognizable. Rather, neuronal groups
play multiple roles. My red detectors are activated whenever red is
before me. But when red things are not before me, my red detectors
are available for other recongitional labor- purple and orange
detection, for example.

Fifth, a neuronal system functioning according to principles of
ontogenic (lifespan) selection, as opposed to phylogenic
(species-level) selection, is fluid in several repects: (1) It can
gain, retain, revise, and abandon all sorts of thoughts, ideas,
desires, and intentions in the course of a life. (2) The system can
lose certain neurons to death, or in a labor dispute, one function
can lose neurons to some other function, without any loss in
functional capacity. If the capacity to recognize a banana as
edible is subserved by parallel activity in numerous recurrent
layers of neuronal groups, then all manner of degradation and loss
of members is compatible with continuous high performance. Neuronal
destruction can, of course, reach a point where the amount of
neuronal degradation is great enough to lead to functional
incapacitation in certain domains, as it does, for example, in
Alzheimer's patients. (3) Neuronal dedication to a task is not
fixed for all time once the neuronal group subserving the
recognitional or motor task in question is well honed. For example,
the neuronal group responsible for pressure detection on two
adjacent fingers wil "segregate into groups that at any one time
are nonoverlapping and have sharp boundaries" (Edelman 1989,
52). But these dedicated groups can shift boundaries over time
because of differential experience, or possibly even
randomly. Imagine the boundary between the United States and Canada
shifting several miles one way or the other each day along its
entire expanse (Calvin 1990, 175).


amitabha mukerjee (mukerjee [at-symbol] gmail) 2012 Feb 11